REPORT FROM IRON MOUNTAIN: ON THE
POSSIBILITY AND DESIRABILITY OF PEACE
With introductory material by Leonard
C. Lewin
The Dial Press, Inc. 1967
New York...
Library of Congress Catalog card
Number 67-27553 Printed in the U.S.
CONTENTS:
-
Forward -- vii
-
Background Information -- xvii
-
Statement by "John Doe" -- xxxi
-
The Report of the Special Study Group
-
Letter of Transmittal -- 3
-
Introduction -- 7
-
Section 1. Scope of the Study -- 11
-
Section 2. Disarmament and the Economy --
17
-
Section 3. Disarmament Scenarios -- 23
-
Section 4. War & Peace as Social
Systems -- 27
-
Section 5. The Functions of War -- 33
-
Section 6. Substitutes for the Functions
of War -- 57
-
Section 7. Summary and Conclusions -- 79
-
Section 8. Recommendations -- 95
-
NOTES -- 103
FOREWORD
"John Doe," as I will call him in this book for
reasons that will be made clear, is a professor at a large university in the
Middle West. His field is one of the social sciences, but I will not identify
him beyond this. He telephoned me one evening last winter, quite unexpectedly;
we had not been in touch for several years. He was in New York for a few days,
he said, and there was something important he wanted to discuss with me. He
wouldn't say what it was. We met for lunch the next day at a midtown
restaurant.
He was obviously disturbed. He made small talk for
half an hour, which was quite out of character, and I didn't press him. Then,
apropos of nothing, he mentioned a dispute between a writer and a prominent
political family that had been in the headlines. What, he wanted to know, were
my views on "freedom of information"? How would I qualify them? And so on. My
answers were not memorable, but they seemed to satisfy him. Then, quite
abruptly, he began to tell me the following story:
Early in August of 1963, he said, he found a
message on his desk that a "Mrs. Potts" had called him from Washington. When he
returned the call, a MAN answered immediately, and told Doe, among other things,
that he had been selected to serve on a commission "of the highest importance."
Its objective was to determine, accurately and realistically, the nature of the
problems that would confront the United States if and when a condition of
"permanent peace" should arrive, and to draft a program for dealing with this
contingency. The man described the unique procedures that were to govern the
commission's work and that were expected to extend its scope far beyond that of
any previous examination of these problems.
Considering that the caller did not precisely
identify either himself or his agency, his persuasiveness must have been a truly
remarkable order. Doe entertained no serious doubts of the bona fides of the
project, however, chiefly because of his previous experience with the excessive
secrecy that often surrounds quasi-governmental activities. In addition, the man
at the other end of the line demonstrated an impressively complete and
surprisingly detailed knowledge of Doe's work and personal life. He also
mentioned the names of others who were to serve with the group; most of them
were known to Doe by reputation. Doe agreed to take the assignment --- he felt
he had no real choice in the matter --- and to appear the second Saturday
following at Iron Mountain, New York. An airline ticket arrived in his mail the
next morning.
The cloak-and-daggar tone of this convocation was
further enhanced by the meeting place itself. Iron Mountain, located near the
town of Hudson, is like something out of Ian Fleming or E.Phillips Oppenheim. It
is an underground nuclear hideout for hundreds of large American corporations.
Most of them use it as an emergency storage vault for important documents. But a
number of them maintain substitute corporate headquarters as well, where
essential personnel could presumably survive and continue to work after an
attack. This latter group includes such firms as Standard Oil of New Jersey,
Manufacturers Hanover Trust, and Shell.
I will leave most of the story of the operations of
the Special Study Group, as the commission was formally called, for Doe to tell
in his own words ("Background Information"). At this point it is necessary to
say only that it met and worked regularly for over two and a half years, after
which it produced a Report. It was this document, and what to do about it, that
Doe wanted to talk to me about.
The Report, he said, had been suppressed --- both
by the Special Study Group itself and by the government INTERAGENCY committee to
which it had been submitted. After months of agonizing, Doe had decided that he
would no longer be party to keeping it secret. What he wanted from me was advice
and assistance in having it published. He gave me his copy to read, with the
express understanding that if for any reason I were unwilling to become
involved, I would say nothing about it to anyone else.
I read the Report that same night. I will pass over
my own reactions to it, except to say that the unwillingness of Doe's associates
to publicize their findings became readily understandable. What had happened was
that they had been so tenacious in their determination to deal comprehensively
with the many problems of transition to peace that the original questions asked
of them were never quite answered. Instead, this is what they concluded:
Lasting peace, while no theoretically impossible,
is probably unattainable; even if it could be achieved it would almost certainly
not be in the best interestes of a stable society to achieve it.
That is the gist of what they say. Behind their
qualified academic language runs this general argument: War fills certain
functions essential to the stability of our society; until other ways of filling
them are developed, the war system must be maintained -- and improved in
effectiveness.
It is not surprising that the Group, in its Letter
of Transmittal, did not choose to justify its work to "the lay reader, unexposed
to the exigencies of higher political or military responsibility." Its Report
was addressed, deliberately, to unnamed government administrators of high rank;
it assumed - considerable politicial sophistication from this select audience.
To the general reader, therefore, the substance of the document may be even more
unsettling than its conclusions. He may not be prepared for some of its
assumptions -- for instance, that most medical advances are viewed more as
problems than as progress; or that poverty is necessary and desirable, public
postures by politicians to the contrary notwithstanding; or that standing armies
are, among other things social-welfare institutions in exactly the same sense as
are old-people's homes and mental hospitals. It may strike him as odd to find
the probably explanation of "flying saucer" incidents disposed of en passant in
less than a sentence. He may be less surprised to find that the space program
and the "controversial antimissile missile and fallout shelter programs are
understood to have the spending of vast sums of money, not the advancement of
science or national defense, as their principal goals, and to learn that
"military" draft policies are only remotely concerned with defense.
He may be offended to find the organized repression
of minority groups, and even the reestablishment of slavery, seriously (and on
the whole favorably discussed as possible aspects of a world at peace. He is not
likely to take kindly to the notion of the deliberate intensification of air and
water pollution (as part of a program leading to peace), even when the reason
for considering it is made clear. That a world without war will have to turn
sooner rather than later to universal test-tube procreation will be less
disturbing, if no more appealing. But few readers will not be taken aback, at
least, by a few lines in th Report's conclusions, repeated in its formal
recommendations, that suggest that the long-range planning--and "budgeting" --
of the "optimum" number of lives to be destroyed annuallly in overt warfare is
high on the Group's list of priorities for government action.
I cite these few examples primarily to warn the
general reader what he can expect. The statesmen and strategists for whose eyes
the Report was intended obviously need no such protective admonition.
This book, of course, is evidence of my response to
Doe's request. After carefully considering the problems that might confront the
publisher of the Report, we took it to The Dial Press. There, its significance
was immediately recognized, and, more important, we were given firm assurances
that no outside pressures of any sort would be permitted to interfere with its
publication.
It should be made clear that Doe does not disagree
with the substance of the Report, which represents as genuine consensus in all
important respects. He constituted a minority of one -- but only on the issue of
disclosing it to the general public. A look at how the Group dealt with this
question will be illuminating
The debate took place at the Group's last full
meeting before the Report was written, late in March, 1966, and again at Iron
Mountain. Two facts must be kept in mind, by way of background. The first is
that the Special Study Group had never been explicitly charged with or sworn to
secrecy, either when it was convened or at any time thereafter. The second is
that the Group had neverthe-less operated as if it had been. This was assumed
from the circumstances of its inception and from the tone of its instructions.
(The Group's acknowledgment of help from "the many persons....who contributed so
greatly to our work" is somewhat equivocal; these persons were not told the
nature of the project for which their special resources of information were
solicited.)
Those who argued the case for keeping the Report
secret were admittedly motivated by fear of the explosive political effects that
could be expected from publicity. For evidence, they pointed to the suppression
of the far less controversial report of then-Senator Hubert Humphrey's
subcommittee on disarmament in 1962. (Subcommittee members had reportedly feared
that it might be used by Communist propagandists, as Senator Stuart Symington
put it, to "back up the Marxian theory that was production was the reason for
the success of capitalism.") Similar political precautions had been taken with
the better-known Gaither Report in 1957, and even with the so-called Moynihan
Report in 1965.
Furthermore, they insisted, a distinction must be
made between serious studies, which are normally classified unless and until
policy makers decide to release them, and conventional "showcase" projects,
organized to demonstrate a political leadership's concerns about an issue and to
deflect the energy of those pressing for action on it. (The example used,
because some of the Group had participated in it, was a "While House Conference"
on intended cooperation, disarmament, etc., which had been staged late in 1965
to offset complaints about escalation of Vietnam War.)
Doe acknowledges this distinction, as well as the
strong possibility of public misunderstanding. But he feels that if the
sponsoring agency had wanted to mandate secrecy it could have done so at the
outset. It could also have assigned the project to one of the government's
established "think tanks," which normally work on a classified basis. He scoffed
at fear of public reaction, which could have no lasting effect on long-range
measures that might be taken to implement the Group's proposals, and derided the
Group's abdication of responsibility for its opinions and conslusions. So far as
he was concerned, there was such a thing as a public right to know what was
being done on its behalf; the burden of proof was on those who would abridge
it.
If my account seems to give Doe the better of the
argument, despite his failure to convince his colleagues, so be it. My
participation in this book testifies that I am not neutral. In my opinion, the
decision of the Special Study Group to censor its own findings was not merely
timid but presumptuos. But the refusal, as of this writing, of the agencies for
which the Report was prepared to release it themselves raises broader questions
of public policy. Such questions center on the continuing use of self-serve
definitions of "security" to avoid possible political embarrassment. It is
ironic how oftern this practice backfires.
I should state, for the record, that I do not share
the attitudes toward war and peace, life and death, and survival of the species
manifested in the Report. Few readers will. In human terms, it is an outrageous
document. But it does represent a serious and challenging effort to define an
enormous problem. And it explains, or certainly appears to explain, aspects of
American policy otherwise incomprehensible by the ordinary standards of common
sense. What we may think of these explanations is something else, but it seems
to me that we are entitled to know not only what they are but whose they
are.
By "whose" I don't mean merely the names of the
authors of the Report. Much more important, we have a right to know to what
extent their assumptions of social necessity are shared by the decision-makers
in our government. Which do they accept and which do they reject? However
disturbing the answers, only full and frank discussion offers any conceivable
hope of solving the problems raised by the Special Study Group in their Report
from Iron Mountain.
L.C.L. New York June 1967
BACKGROUND INFORMATION
[The following account of the workings of the
Special Study Group is taken verbatim from a series of tape recorded interviews
I had with "John Doe." The transcript has been edited to minimize the intrusion
of my questions and comments, as well as for length, and the sequence has been
revised in the interest of continuity. L.C.L.]
HOW WAS THE GROUP FORMED?
...The general idea for it, for this kind of study
dates back at least to 1961. It started with some of the new people who came in
with the Kennedy administration, mostly, I think, with McNamara, Bundy, and
Rusk. They were impatient about many things....One of them was that no really
serious work had been done about planning for peace---a long-range peace, that
is, with long- rang planning.
Everything that had been written on the subject
[before 1961] was super- ficial. There was insufficient appreciation of the
scope of the problem. The main reason for this, of course, was that the idea of
a real peace in the world, general disarmament and so on, was looked on as
utopian. Or even crack- pot. This is still true, and it's easy enough to
understand when you look at what's going on in the world today....It was
reflected in the studies that had been made up to that time. They were not
realistic...
The idea of the Special Study, the exact form it
would take, was worked out early in '63...The settlement of the Cuban missile
affair had something to do with it, but what helped most to get it moving were
the big changes in military spending that were being planned.....Plants being
closed, relocations, and so forth. Most of it wasn't made public until much
later....
[I understand] it took a long time to select the
people for the Group. The calls didn't go out until the summer......
WHO MADE THE SELECTION?
That's something I can't tell you. I wasn't
involved with the preliminary planning. The first I knew of it was when I was
called myself. But three of the people had been in on it, and what the rest of
us know we learned from them, about what went on earlier. I do know that it
started very informally. I don't know what particular government agency approved
the project.
WOULD YOU CARE TO MAKE A GUESS?
All right---I think it was an ad hoc committee, at
the cabinet level, or near it. It had to be. I suppose they gave the
organizational job--making arrangements, paying the bills, and so on---to
somebody from the State or Defense of the National Security Council. Only one of
us was in touch with Washington, and I wasn't the one. But I can tell you that
very, very few people knew about us....For instance, there was the Ackley
Committee. It was set up after we were. If you read their report---the same old
tune---economic reconversino, turning sword plants into plowshare factories...I
think you'll wonder if even the President knew about our Group. The Ackley
Committee certainly didn't.
IS THAT POSSIBLE, REALLY? I MEAN THAT NOT EVEN THE
PRESIDENT KNEW OF YOUR COMMISSION?
Well, I don't think there's anything odd about the
government attacking a problem at two different levels. Or even about two or
three [government] agencies working at cross-purposes. It happens all the time.
Perhaps the President did know. And I don't mean to denigrate the Ackley
Committee, but it was exactly that narrowness of approach that we were supposed
to get away from.......
You have to remember -- you've read the
Report---that what they wanted from us was a different kind of thinking. It was
a matter of approach. Herman Kahn calls is "Byzantine"--no agonizing over
cultural and religious values. No moral posturing. It's the kind of thinking
that Rand and the Hudson Institure and I.D.A. (Institute for Defense Analysis.)
brought into war planning...What they asked up to do, and I think we did it, was
to give the same kind of treat- ment to the hypothetical nuclear war...We may
have gone further than they expected, but once you establish your premises and
your logic you can't turn back....
Kahn's books, for example, are misunderstood, at
least by laymen. They shock people. But you see, what's improtant about them is
not his conclusions, or his opinions. It's the method. He has done more than
anyone else I can think of to get the general public accustomed to the style of
modern military think- ing.....Today it's possible for a columnist to write
about "counterforce strategy" and "minimum deterrance" and "credible firststrike
capability" with- out having to explain every other word. He can write about war
and strategy without getting bogged down in questions or morality.......
The other big difference about or work is breadth.
The Report speaks for itself. I can't say that we took every relevant aspect of
life and society into account, but I don't think we missed anything
essential...
WHY WAS THE PROJECT GIVEN TO AN OUTSIDE
COMMISSION? WHY COULDN'T IT HAVE BEEN HANDLED BY AN APPROPRIATE GOVERNMENT
AGANCY?
I think that's obvious, or should be. The kind of
thinking wanted from our Group just isn't to be had in a formal government
operation. Too many cont- straints. Too many inhibitions. This isn't a new
problem. Why else would outfits like Rand and Hudson stay in business? Any
assignment that's at all sophisticated is almost always given to an outside
group. This is true even in the State Department, in the "gray" operations,
those that are supposed to be unofficial, but are really as official as can be.
Also with the C.I.A....
For our study, even the private research centers
were too institutional... A lot of thought went into making sure that our
thinking would be unrestricted. All kinds of little things. The way we were
called into the Group, the places we met, all kinds of subtle devices to remind
us. For instance, even our name, the Special Study Group. You know government
names. Wouldn't you think we'd have been called "Operation Olive Branch," or
"Project Pacifica," or something like that? Nothing like that for us---too
allusive, too suggestive. And no minutes of our meetings---too inhibiting....
About who might be reading them. Of course, we took notes for our own use. And
among ourselves, we usually called ourselves "The Iron Mountain Boys," or "Our
Thing," or whatever came to mind........
WHAT CAN YOU TELL ME ABOUT THE MEMBERS OF THE
GROUP?
I'll have to stick to generalities....There were
fifteen of us. The important thing was that we represented a very wide range of
disciplines. And not all academic. People from the natural sciences, the social
sciences, even the humanities. We had a lawyer and a businessman. Also, a
professional war planner. Also, you should know that everyone in the Group had
done work of distinction in at least two different fields. The interdisciplinary
element was built in.....
It's true that there were no women in the Group,
but I don't think that was significant.....We were all American citizens, of
course. And all, I can say, in very good health, at least when we began.... You
see, the first order of business, at the first meeting, was the reading of
dossiers. They were very detailed, and not just professional, but also personal.
They included medical histories. I remember one very curious thing, for whatever
it's worth. Most of us, and that includes me, had a record of abnormally high
uric acid con- centrations in the blood...... None of us had ever had this
experience, of a public inspection of credentials, or medical reports. It was
very disturbing...
But it was deliberate. The reason for it was to
emphasize that we were supposed to make ALL our own decisions on procedure,
without outside rules. This included judging each other's qualifications and
making allowances for possible bias. I don't think it affected our work
directly, but it made the point it was supposed to make...... That we should
ignore absolutely nothing that might conceivably affect our objectivity.
[At this point I persuaded Doe that a brief
occupational description of the individual members of the Group would serve a
useful purpose for readers of the Report. The list which follows was worked out
on paper. (It might be more accurate to say it was negotiated)/. The problem was
to give as much relevant information as possible without violating Doe's
commitment to protect his colleagues' anonymity. It turned out to be very
difficult, especially in the cases of those members who are very well known. For
this reason, secondary areas of achievement or repu- tations are usually not
shown.
The simple alphabetical "names" were assigned by
Doe for convenient reference; they bear no intended relation to actual names.
"Able" was the Group's Washington contact. It was he who brought and read the
dossiers, and who most often acted as chairman. He, "Baker," and "Cox" were the
three who had been involved in the preliminary planning. There is no other
significance to the order of listing.
"Arthus Able" is an historian and political
theorist, who has served in government.
"Bernard Baker: is a professor of international law
and a consultant on government operations.
"Charles Cox" is an economist, social critic, and
biographer.
"John Doe."
"Edward Ellis" is a sociologist often involved in
public affairs.
"Frank Fox" is a cultural anthropologist.
"George Green" is a psychologist, educator, and
developer of personnel testing systems.
"Harold Hill" is a psychiatrist, who has conducted
extensive studies of the relationship between individual and group behavior.
"John Jones" is a scholar and literary critic.
"Martin Miller" is a physical chemist, whose work
has received inter- national recognition at the highest level.
"Paul Peters" is a biochemist, who has made
important discoveries bearing on reproductive processes.
"Richard Roe" is a mathematician affiliated with an
independent West Coast research institution.
"Samuel Smith" is an astronomer, physicist, and
communications theorist.
"Thomas Taylor" is a systems analyst and war
planner, who has written extensively on war, peace, and international
relations.
"William White" is an industrialist, who has
undertaken many special government assignments.]
HOW DID THE GROUP OPERATE? I MEAN, WHERE AND WHEN
DID YOU MEET, AND SO FORTH?
We met on the average of once a month. Usually it
was on weekends, and usually for two days. We had a few longer sessions, and one
that lasted only four hours. .... We met all over the country, always at a
different place, except for the first and last times, which were at Iron
Mountain. It was like a traveling seminar....Sometimes at hotels, sometimes at
universities. Twice we met at summer camps, and once at a private estate, in
Virginia. We used a business place in Pittsburgh, and another in Poughkeepsie,
[New York]....We never met in Washington, or on government property
anywhere....Able would announce the times and places two meetings ahead. They
were never changed.....
We didn't divide into subcommittees, or anything
else that formal. But we all took individual assignments between meetings. A lot
of it involved getting information from other people.... Among the fifteen of
us, I don't thing there was anybody in the academic or professional world we
couldn't call on if we wanted to, and we took advantage of it..... We were paid
a very modest per diem. All of it was called "expenses" on the vouchers. We were
told not to report it on our tax returns.... The checks were drawn on a special
account of Able's at a New York bank. He signed them....I don't know what the
study cost. So far as our time and travel were concerned, it couldn't have come
to more than the low six-figure range. But the big item must have been computer
time, and I have no idea how high this ran......
YOU SAY THAT YOU DON'T THINK YOUR WORK WAS
AFFECTED BY PROFESSIONAL BIAS. WHAT ABOUT POLITICAL AND PHILOSOPHICAL BIAS? IS
IT POSSIBLE TO DEAL WITH QUESTIONS OF WAR AND PEACE WITHOUT REFLECTING PERSONAL
VALUES?
Yes, it is. I can understand your skepticism. But
if you had been at any of our meetings you'd have had a very hard time figuring
out who were the liberals and who were the conservatives, or who were hawks and
who were doves. There IS such a thing as objectivity, and I think we had it... I
don't say no one had any emotional reaction to what we were doing. We all did,
to some extent. As a matter of fact, two members had heart attacks after we were
finished, and I'll be the first to admit it probably wasn't a coincidence.
YOU SAID YOU MADE UP YOUR OWN GROUND RULES. WHAT
WERE THESE GROUND RULES?
The most important were informality and unanimity .
By informality I mean that our discussions were open-ended. We went as far
afield as any one of us thought we had to. For instance, we spent a lot of time
on the relationship between military recruitment policies and industrial
employment. Before we were finished with it, we'd gone through the history of
western penal codes and any number of comparative psychiatric studies [of
draftees and volunteers]. We looked over the organization of the Inca empire. We
determined the effects of automation on underdeveloped societies....It was all
relevant....
By unanimity, I don't mean that we kept taking
votes, like a jury. I mean that we stayed with every issue until we had what the
Quakers call a "sense of the meeting." It was time-consuming. But in the long
run it saved time. Eventually we all got on the same wavelength, so to
speak.....
Of course we had differences, and big ones,
especially in the beginning... For instance, in Section I you might think we
were merely clarifying our instructions. Not so; it took a long time before we
all agreed to a strict interpretation.... Roe and Taylor deserve most of the
credit for this... There are many things in the Report that look obvious now,
but didn't seem so obvious then. For instance, on the relationship of war to
social systems. The original premise was conventional, from Clausewitz. ....
That war was an "instrument" of broader political values. Able was the only one
who challenged this, at first. Fox called his position "perverse." Yet it was
Fox who furnished most of the data that led us all to agree with Able
eventually. I mention this be- cause I think it's a good example of the way we
worked. A triumph of method over cliche...... I certainly don't intend to go
into details about who took what side about what, and when. But I will say, to
give credit where due, that only Roe, Able, Hill and Taylor were able to see, at
the beginning, where our method was taking us.
BUT YOU ALWAYS REACHED AGREEMENT, EVENTUALLY?
Yes. It's a unanimous report... I don't mean that
our sessions were always harmonious. Some of them were rough. The last six
months there was a lot of quibbling about small points... We'd been under
pressure for a long time, we'd been working together too long. It was
natural.....that we got on each other's nerves. For a while Able and Taylor
weren't speaking to each other. Miller threatened to quit. But this all passed.
There were no important differences...
HOW WAS THE REPORT ACTUALLY WRITTEN? WHO DID THE
WRITING?
We all had a hand in the first draft. Jones and
Able put it together, and then mailed it around for review before working out a
final version... The only problems were the form it should take and whom we were
writing it for. And, of course, the question of disclosure.... [Doe's comments
on this point are summarized in the introduction.]
YOU MENTIONED A "PEACE GAMES" MANUAL. WHAT ARE
PEACE GAMES?
I wanted to say something about that. The Report
barely mentions it. "Peace games" is a method we developed during the course of
the study. It's a forecasting technique, an information system. I'm very excited
about it. Even if nothing is done about our recommendations--which is
conceivable--this is something that can't be ignored. It will revolutionize the
study of social problems. It's a by-product of the study. We needed a fast,
dependable procedure to approximate the effects of disparate social phenomena on
other social phenomena. We got it. It's in a primitive phase, but it works.
HOW ARE PEACE GAMES PLAYED? ARE THEY LIKE RAND'S
WAR GAMES?
You don't "play" peace games, like chess or
Monopoly, any more than you play war games with toy soldiers. You use computers.
It's a programming system. A computer "language," like Fortran, or Algol, or
Jovial.... Its advantage is its superior capacity to interrelate data with no
apparent common points of reference.... A simple analogy is likely to be
misleading. But I can give you some examples. For instance, supposing I asked
you to figure out what effect a moon landing by U.S. astronauts would have on an
election in, say, Sweden. Or what effect a change in the draft law--a specific
change--would have on the value of real estate in downtown Manhattan? Or a
certain change in college entrance requirements in the United States on the
British shipping industry?
You would probably say, first, that there would be
no effect to speak of, and second, that there would be no way of telling. But
you'd be wrong on both counts. In each case there would be an effect, and the
peace games method could tell you what it would be, quantitatively. I didn't
take these examples out of the air. We used them in working out the
method....Essentiallly, it's an elaborate high-speed trial-and-error system for
determining working algorithms. Like most sophisticated types of computer
problem-solving...
A lot of the "games" of this kind you read about
are just glorified and conversational exercises. They really are games, and
nothing more. I just saw one reported in the Canadian Computer Society Bulletin,
called a "Vietnam Peace Game." They use simulation techniques, but the
programming hypotheses are speculative....
The idea of a problem-solving system like this is
not original with us. ARPA (the Advanced Research Projects Agency, of the
Department of Defense DoD.) has been working on something like it. So has
General Electric, in California. There are others..... We were successful not
because we know more than they do about programming, which we don't, but because
we leaned how to formulate the problems accurately. It goes back to the old saw.
You can always find the answer if you know the right question.....
SUPPOSING YOU HADN'T DEVELOPED THIS METHOD. WOULD
YOU HAVE COME TO THE SAME CONCLUSIONS IN THE REPORT?
Certainly. But it would have taken many times
longer..But please don't misunderstand my enthusiasm [about the peace games
method]. With all due respect to the effects of computer technology on modern
thinking, basic judgments must still be made by human beings. The peace games
technique isn't responsible for our Report. We are.
STATEMENT BY "JOHN DOE"
Contrary to the decision of the Special Study
Group, of which I was a member, I have arranged for the general release of our
Report. I am grateful to Mr. Leonard C. Lewin for his invaluable assistance in
making this possible, and to The Dial Press for accepting the challenge of
publication. Responsibility for taking this step, however, is mine and mine
alone.
I am well aware that my action may be taken as a
breach of faith by some of my former colleagues. But in my view my
responsibility to the society for which I am a part supersedes any self-assumed
obligation on the part of fifteen individual men. Since our Report can be
considered on its merits, it is not necessary for me to disclose their identity
to accomplish my purpose. Yet I gladly abandon my own anonymity it is were
possible to do so without at the same time comprising theirs, to defend our work
publicly if and when they release me from this personal bond.
But this is secondary. What is needed now, and
needed badly, is widespread public discussion and debate about the elements of
war and the problems of peace. I hope that publication of this Report will serve
to initiate it.
THE REPORT OF THE SPECIAL STUDY GROUP
LETTER OF TRANSMITTAL
To the convener of this Group:
Attached is the Report of the Special Study Group
established by you in August, 1963, 1) to consider the problems involved in the
contigency of a transition to a general condition of peace, and 2) to recommend
procedures for dealing with this contingency. For the covenience of nontechnical
readers we have elected to submit our statistical supporting data, totaling 604
exhibits, separately, as well as a preliminary manual of the "peace games"
method devised during the course of our study.
We have compelted our assignment to the best of our
ability, subject to the limitations of time and resources available to us. Our
conclusions of fact and our recommendations are unanimous; those of use who
differ in certain secondary respects from the findings set forth herein do not
consider these differences sufficient to warrant the filing of a minority
report. It is our earnest hope that the fruits of our deliberations will be of
value to our government in its efforts to provide leadership to the nation in
solving the complex and far-reaching problems we have examined, and that our
recommendations for subsequent Presidential action in this area will be
adopted.
Because of the unusual circumstances surrounding
the establishment of this Group, and in view of the nature of its findings, we
do not recommend that this Report be released for publication. It is our
affirmative judgment that such action would not be in the public interest. The
uncertain advantages of public discussion of our conclusions and recommendations
are, in our opinion, greatly outweighed by the clear and predictable danger of a
crisis in public confidence which untimely publication of this Report might be
expected to provoke. The likelihood that a lay reader, unexposed to the
exigencies of higher political or military responsibility, will misconstrue the
purpose of this project, and the intent of its participants, seems obvious. We
urge that circulation of this Report be closely restricted to those whose
responsibilities require that they be apprised of its contents.
We deeply regret that the necessity of anonymity, a
prerequisite to our Group's unhindered pursuit of its objectives, precludes
proper acknowledgment of our gratitude to the many persons in and out of
government who contributed so greatly to our work.
FOR THE SPECIAL STUDY GROUP
[signature withheld for publication]
30 SEPTEMBER, 1966
INTRODUCTION
The Report which follows summarizes the results of
a two-and-a-half-year study of the broad problems to be anticipated in the event
of general trans- formation of American society to a condition lacking its most
critical current characteristics: its capability and readiness to make war when
doing so is judged necessary or desirable by its political leadership.
Our work has been predicated on the belief that
some kind of general peace may soon be negotiable. The de facto admission of
Communist China into the United Nations now appears to be only a few years away
at most. It has become increasinly manifest that conflicts of American national
interest with those of China and the Soviet Union are susceptible of political
solution, despite the superficial contraindictions of the current Vietnam war,
of the threats of an attack on China, and of the necessarily hostile tenor of
day-to-day foreign policy statements. It is also obvious that differences
involving other nations can be readily resolved by the three great powers
whenever they arrive at a stable peace among themselves. It is not necessary,
for the purposes of our study, to assume that a general detente of this sort
will come about---and we make no such argument--but only that it may.
It is surely no exaggeration to say that a
condition of general world peace would lead to changes in the social structures
of the nations of the world of unparalleled and revolutionary magnitude. The
economic impact of general disarmament, to name only the most obvious
consequence of peace, would revise the production and distribution patterns of
the globe to a degree that would make changes of the past fifty years seem
insignificant. Political, sociological, cultural, and ecological changes would
be equally far-reaching. What has motivated our study of these contingencies has
been the growing sense of thoughtful men in and out of government that the world
is totally unprepared to meet the demands of such a situation.
We had originally planned, when our study was
initiated, to address ourselves to these two broad questions and their
components: What can be expected if peace comes? What should we be prepared to
do about it? But as our investigation proceeded, it became apparent that certain
other questions had to be faced. What, for instance, are the real functions of
war in modern societies, beyond the ostensible ones of defending and advancing
the "national interests" of nations? In the absence of war, what other
institutions exist or might be devised to fulfill these functions? Granting that
a "peaceful" settlement of disputes is within the range of current international
relationships, is the abolition of war, in the broad sense, really possible? If
so, is it necessarily desirable, in terms of social stability? If not, what can
be done to improve the operation of our social system in respect to its
war-readiness?
The word peace, as we have used it in the following
pages, describes a permanent, or quasi-permanent, condition entirely free from
the national exercise, or contemplation, of any form of the organized social
violence, or threat of violence, generally known as war. It implies total and
general disarmament. It is not used to describe the more familiar condition of
"cold war," "armed peace," or other mere respite, long or short, from armed
conflict. Nor is it used simply as a synonym for the political settlement of
international differences. The magnitude of modern means of mass destruction and
the speed of modern communications require the unqualified working definition
given above; only a generation ago such an absolute description would have seemd
utopian rather than pragmatic. Today, any modification of this definition would
render it almost worthless for our purpose. By the same standard, we have used
the work war to apply interchangeably to conventional ("hot") war, to the
general condition of war preparation or war readiness, and to the general "war
system." The sense intended is made clear in context.
The first section of our Report deals with its
scope and with the assumptions on which our study was based. The second
considers the effects of disarmament on the economy, the subject of most peace
research to date. The third takes up so-called "disarmament scenarios" which
have been proposed. The fourth, fifth, and sixth examine the nonmilitary
functions of war and the problems they raise for a viable transition to peace;
here will be found some indications of the true dimensions of the problem, not
previously coordinated in any other study. In the seventh section we summarize
our findings, and in the eight we set forth our recommendations for what we
believe to be a practical and necessary course of action.
SECTION 1 - SCOPE OF THE STUDY
When The Special Study Group was established in
August, 1963, its members were instructed to govern their deliberations in
accordance with three principal criteria. Briefly stated, they were these: 1)
military-style objectivity; 2) avoidance of preconceived value assumptions; 3)
inclusion of all revelant areas of theory and data.
These guideposts are by no means as obvious as they
may appear at first glance, and we believe it necessary to indicate clearly how
they were to inform our work. For they express succinctly the limitations of
previous "peace studies," and imply the nature of both government and unofficial
dissatisfaction with these earlier efforts. It is not our intention here to
minimize the significance of the work of our predecessors, or to belittle the
quality of their contributions. What we have tried to do, and believe we have
done, is extend their scope. We hope that our conclusions may serve in turn as a
starting point for still broader and more detailed examinations of every aspect
of the problems of transition to peace and of the questions which must be
answer- ed before such a transition can be allowed to get under way.
It is a truism that objectivity is more often an
intention expressed than an attitude achieved, but the intention---conscious,
unambiguous, and constantly self-critical -- is a precondition to its
achievement. We believe it no accident that we were charged to use a "military
contingency" model for our study, and we owe a considerable debt to the civilian
war planning agencies for their pioneering work in the objective examination of
the contingencies of nuclear war. There is no such precedent in the peace
studies. Much of the usefulness of even the most elaborate and carefully
reasoned programs for economic conversion to peace, for example, has been
vitiated by a wishful eagerness to demonstrate that peace is not only possible,
but even cheap or easy. One official report is replete with references to the
critical role of "dynamic optimism" on economic developments, and goes on to
submit, as evidence, that it "would be hard to imagine that the American people
would not respond very positively to an agreed and safeguarded program to
substitute an internatinal rule of law and order," etc. Anothe line of argument
frequently taken is that disarmament would entail comparatively little
disruption of the economy, since it need only be partial; we will deal with this
approach later. Yet genuine objectivity in war studies is often critized as
inhuman. As Herman Kahn, the writer on strategic studies best known to the
general public, put it: "Critics frequently object to the icy rationality of the
Hudson Institute, the Rand Corporation, and other such organizations. I'm always
tempted to ask in reply, `Would you prefer a warm, human error? Do you feel
better with a nice emotional mistake.'" And, as Secretary of Defense Robert S.
McNamara has pointed out, in reference to facing up to the possibility of
nuclear war, "Some people are afraid even to look over the edge. But in a
thermonuclear war we cannot afford any political acrophobia." Surely it would be
self-evident that this applies equally to the opposite prospect, but so far no
one has taken more than a timid glance over the brink of peace.
An intention to avoid preconceived value judgments
is if anything even more productive of self-delusion. We claim no immunity, as
individuals, from this type of bias, but we have made a continuously
self-conscious effort to deal with the problems of peace without, for exampel,
considering that a condition of peace is per se "good" or "bad." This has not
been easy, but it has been obligatory; to our knowledge, it has not been done
before. Previous studies have taken the desirability of peace, the importance of
human life, the superiority of democratic institutions, the greatest "good" for
the greatest number, the "dignity" of the individual, the desirability of
maximum health and longevity, and other such wishful premises as axiomatic
values necessary for the justification of a study of peace issues. We have not
found them so. We have attempted to apply the standards of physical science to
our thinking, the principal characteristic of which is not quantification, as is
popularly believd, but that, in Whitehead's words, "...it ignores all judgments
of value; for instance, all esthetic and moral judgments." Yet it is obvious
that any serious investigation of a problem, however "pure," must be informed by
some normative standard. In this case it has been simply the survival of human
society in general, of Amerian society in particular, and, as a corollary to
survival, the stability of this society.
It is interesting, we believe, to note that the
most dispassionate planners of nuclear strategy also recognize that the
stability of society is the one bedrock value that cannot be avoided. Secretary
McNamara has defended the need for American nuclear superiority on the grounds
that it "makes possible a strategy designed to preserve the fabric of our
societies if war should occur." A former member ofthe Department of State policy
planning staff goes further. "A more precise word for peace, in terms of the
practical world, is stability. ... Today the great nuclear panoplies are
essential elements in such stability as exists. Our present purpose must be to
continue the process of learning how to live with them." We, of course, do not
equate stability with peace, but we accept it as the one common assumed
objective of both peace and war.
The third criterion-breadth-has taken us still
farther afield from peace studies made to date. It is obvious to any layman that
the economic patterns of a warless world will be drastically different from
those we live with today, and it is equally obvious that the political
relationships of nations will not be those we have learned to take for granted,
sometimes described as a global version of the adversary system of our common
law. But the social implications of peace extend far beyond its putative effects
on national economics and international relations. As we shall show, the
relevance of peace and war to the internal political organization of societies,
to the sociological relationships of their members, to psychological
motivations, to ecological processes, and to cultural values is equally
profound. More important, it is equally critical in assaying the consequences of
a transition to peace, and in deter- mining the feasibility of any transition at
all.
It is not surprising that these less obvious
factors have been generally ignored in peace research. They have not lent
themselves to systematic analysis. They have been difficult, perhaps impossible,
to measure with any degree of assurance that estimates of their effects could be
depended on. They are "intangibles," but only in the sense that abstract
concepts in mathematics are intangible compared to those which can be
quantified. Economic factors, on the other hand, can be measured, at least
superficialy; and international relationships can be verbalized, like law, into
logical sequences.
We do not claim that we have discovered an
infallible way of measuring these other factors, or of assigning them precise
weights in the equation of transition. But we believe we have taken their
relative importance into account to this extent: we have removed them from the
category of the "intangible," hence scientifically suspect and therefore somehow
of secondary importance, and brought them out into the realm of the objective.
The result, we believe, provides a context of realism for the discussion of the
issues relating to the possible transition to peace which up to now has been
missing.
This is not to say that we presume to have found
the answers we were seeking. But we believe that our emphasis on breadth of
scope has made it at least possible to begin to understand the questions.
SECTION 2 - DISARMAMENT AND THE ECONOMY
In this section we shall briefly examine some of
the common features of the studies that have been published dealing with one or
another aspect of the expected impact of disarmament on the American economy.
Whether disarmament is considered as a by-product of peace or as its
precondition, its effect on the national economy will in either case be the most
immediately felt of its consequences. The quasi-mensurable quality of economic
manifestations has given rise to more detailed speculation in this area than in
any other.
General agreement prevails in respect to the more
important economic problems that general disarmament would raise. A short survey
of these problems, rather than a detailed critique of their comparative
significance, is sufficient for our purposes in this Report.
The first factor is that of size. The "world war
industry," as one writer has aptly caled it, accounts for approximately a tenth
of the output of the world's total economy. Although this figure is subject to
fluctuation, the causes of which are themselves subject to regional variation,
it tends to hold fairly steady. The United States, as the world's richest
nation, not only accounts for the largest single share of this expense,
currently upward of $60 billion a year, but also "...has devoted a higher
proportion [emphasis added] of its gross national product to its military
establishment than any other major free world nation. This was true even before
our increased expenditures in Southeast Asia." Plans for economic conversion
that minimize the economic magnitude of the problem do so only by rationalizing,
however persuasively, the maintenance of a substantial residual military budget
under some euphemized classification.
Conversion of military expenditures to other
purposes entails a number of difficulties. The most serious stems from the
degree of rigid specialization that characterizes modern war production, best
exemplified in nuclear and missile technology. This constituted no fundamental
problem after World War II, nor did the question of free-market consumer demand
for "conventinal" items of consumption---those good and services consumers had
already been conditioned to require. Today's situation is qualitatively
different in both respects.
This inflexibility is geographical and
occupational, as well as industrial, a fact which has led most analysts of the
economic impact of disarmament to focus their attention on phased plans for the
relocation of war industry personnel and capital installations as much as on
proposals for developing new patterns of consumption. One serious flaw common to
such plans is the kind called in the natural sciences the "macroscopic error."
An implicit presumption is made that a total national plan for conversion
differs from a community program to cope with the shutting down of a "defense
facility" only in degree. We find no reason to believe that this is the case,
nor that a general enlargement of such local programs, however well thought out
in terms of housing, occupational retraining, and the like, can be applied on a
national scale. A national economy can absorb amost any number of subsidiary
reorganizations within its total limits, providing there is no basic change in
its own structure. General disarmament, which would require such basic changes,
lends itself to no valid smaller-scale analogy.
Even more questionable are the models proposed for
the retaining labor for nonarmaments occupations. Putting aside for the moment
the unsolved questions dealing with the nature of new distribution
patterns---retraining for what?-- the increasingly specialized job skills
associated with war industry production are further depreciated by the
accelerating inroads of the industrial techniques loosely described as
"automation." It is not too much to say that general disarmament would require
the scrapping of a critical proportion of the most highly developed occupational
specialites in the economy. The political difficulties inherent in such an
"adjustment" would make the outcries resulting from the closing of a few
obsolete military and naval installatins in 1964 sound like a whisper.
In general, discussions of the problem of
conversion have been characterized by an unwillingness to recognize its special
quality. This is best ecemplified by the 1965 report of the Ackley Committee.
One critic has tellingly pointed out that it blindly assumes that "...nothing in
the arms economy--neither its size, nor its geographical concentration, nor its
highly specialized nature, nor the peculiarties of its market, nor the special
nature of much of its labor force---endows it with any uniqueness when the
necessary time of adjustment comes."
Let us assume, however, despite the lack of
evidence that a viable program for conversion can be developed in the framework
of the existing economy, that the problems noted above can be solved. What
proposals have been offered for utilizing the productive capabilities that
disarmament would presumably release?
The most common held theory is simply that general
economic reinvestment would absorb the greater part of these capabilities. Even
though it is now largely taken for granted (and even by today's equivalent of
traditional laissez-faire economists) taht unprecedented government assistance
(and con- comitant government control) will be needed to solve the "structural"
problems of transition, a general attitude of confidence prevails that new
consumption patterns will take up the slack. What is less clear is the nature of
these patterns.
One school of economists has it that these patterns
will develop on their own. It envisages the equivalent of the arms budget being
returned, under careful control, to the consumer, in the form of tax cuts.
Another, recognizing the undeniable need for increased "consumption" in what is
generally considered the public sector of the economy, stresses vastly increased
government spending in such areas of national concern as health, education, mass
transportation, low-cost housing, water supply, control of the physical
environment, and, stated generally, "poverty."
The mechanisms proposed for controlling the
transition to an arms-free economy are also traditional--changes in both sides
of the federal budget, manipulation of interest rates, etc. We acknowledge the
undeniable value of fiscal tools in a normal cyclical economy, where they
provide leverage to accelerate or brake an existing trend. Their more committed
proponents, however, tend to lose sight of the fact that there is a limit to the
power of these devices to influence fundamental economic forces. They can
provide new incentives in the economy, but they cannot in themselves transform
the production of a billion dollars' worth of missiles a year to the equivalent
in food, clothing, prefabricated houses, or television sets. At bottom, they
reflect the economy; they do not motivate it.
More sophisticated, and less sanguine, analysts
contemplate the diversion of the arms budget to a non-military system equally
remote from the market economy. What the "pyramid-builders" frequently suggest
is the expansion of space-research programs to the dollar level of current
expenditures. This approach has the superficial merit of reducing the size of
the problem of transferability of resources, but introduces other difficulties,
which we will take up in section 6.
Without singling out any one of the several major
studies of the expected impact of disarmament on the economy for special
criticism, we can summarize our objections to them in general terms as
follows:
-
No proposed program for economic conversion to
disarmament sufficiently takes into account the unique magnitude of the required
adjustments it would entail.
-
Proposals to transform arms production into a
beneficent scheme of public works are more the products of wishful thinking than
of realistic understanding of the limits of our existing economic system.
-
Fiscal and monetary measures are inadequate as
controls for the process of transition to an arms-free economy.
-
Insufficient attention has been paid to the
political acceptability of the objectives of the proposed conversion models, as
well as of the political means to be employed in effectuating a transition.
-
No serious consideration has been given, in any
proposed conversion plan, to the fundamental nonmilitary function of war and
armaments in modern society, nor has any explicit attempt been made to devise a
viable substitute for it. This criticism will be developed in sections 5 and 6.
SECTION 3 - DISARMAMENT SCENARIOS
SCENARIOS, as they have come to be called, are
hypothetical constructions of future events. Inevitably, they are composed of
varying proportions of established fact, reasonable inference, and more or less
inspired guesswork. Those which have been suggested as model procedures for
effectuating international arms control and eventual disarmament are necessarily
imaginative, although closely reasoned; in this respect they resemble the "war
games" analyses of the Rand Corporation, with which they share a common
conceptual origin.
All such scenarios that have been seriously put
forth imply a dependence on bilateral or multilateral agreement between the
great powers. In general, they call for a progressive phasing out of gross
armaments, military forces, weapons, and weapons technology, coordinated with
elaborate matching procedures of verification, inspection, and machinery for the
settlement of international disputes. It should be noted that even proponents of
unilateral disarmament qualify their proposals with an implied requirement of
reciprocity, very much in the manner of a scenario of graduated response in
nuclear war. The advantage of unilateral initiative lies in its political value
as an expression of good faith, as well as in its diplomatic function as a
catalyst for formal disarmament negotiations.
The READ model for disarmament (developed by the
Research Program on Economic Adjustments to Disarmament) is typical of these
scenarios. It is a twelve-year program, divided into three-year stages. Each
stage includes a separate phase of: reduction of armed forces; cutbacks of
weapons production, inventories, and foreign military bases; development of
international inspection procedures and control conventiona; and the building up
of a sovereign international disarmament organization. It anticipates a net
matching decline in U.S. defense expenditures of only somewhat more than half
the 1965 level, but a necessary redeployment of some five-sixths of the
defense-dependent labor force.
The economic implications assigned by their authors
to various disarmament scenarios diverge widely. The more conservative models,
like that cited above, emphasize economic as well as military prudence in
postulating elaborate fail-safe disarmament agencies, which themselves require
expenditures substantially substituting for those of the displaced war
industries. Such programs stress the advantages of the smaller economic
adjustment entailed. Others emphasize, on the contrary, the magnitude (and the
opposite advantages) of the savings to be achieved from disarmament. One widely
read analysis estimates the annual cost of the inspection function of general
disarmament throughout the world as only between two and three percent of
current military expenditures. Both types of plan tend to deal with the
anticipated problem of economic reinvestment only in the aggregate. We have seen
no proposed disarmament sequence that correlates the phasing out of specific
kinds of military spending with specific new forms of substitute spending.
Without examining disarmament scenarios in greater
detail, we may characterize them with these general comments:
-
Given genuine agreement of intent among the great
powers, the scheduling of arms control and elimination presents no inherently
insurmountable procedural problems. Any of several proposed sequences might
serve as the basis for multilateral agreement or for the first step in
unilateral arms reduction.
-
No major power can proceed with such a program,
however, until it has developed an economic conversion plan fully integrated
with each phase of disarmament. No such plan has yet been developed in the
United States.
-
Furthermore, disarmament scenarios, like proposals
for economic conversion, make no allowance for the non-military functions of war
in modern societies, and offer no surrogate for these necessary functions. One
partial exception is a proposal for the "unarmed forces of the United States,"
which we will consider in section 6.
SECTION 4 - WAR AND PEACE AS SOCIAL SYSTEMS
We have dealt only sketchily with proposed
disarmament scenarios and economic analyses, but the reason for our seemingly
casual dismissal of so much serious and sophisticated work lies in no disrespect
for its competence. It is rather a question of relevance. To put it plainly, all
these programs, however detailed and well developed, are abstractions. The most
carefully reasoned disarmament sequence inevitably reads more like the rules of
a game or a classroom exercise in logic than like a prognosis of real events in
the real world. This is as true of today's complex proposals as it was of the
Abbe de St. Pierre's "Plane for Perpetual Peace in Eurpope" 250 years ago.
Some essential element has clearly been lacking in
all these schemes. One of our first tasks was to try to bring this missing
quality into definable focus, and we believe we have succeeded in doing so. We
find that at the heart of every peace study we have examined--from the modest
technoligical proposal (e.g., to convert a poison gas plant to the production of
"socially useful" equivalents) to the most eleborate scenario for universal
peace in out time--lies one common fundamental misconception. It is the source
of the miasma of unreality surrounding such plans. It is the incorrect
assumption that war, as an institution, is subordinate to the social systems it
is believed to serve.
This misconceptino, although profound and
far-reaching, is entirely comprehensible. Few social cliches are so
unquestioningly accepted as the notion that war is an extension of diplomacy (or
of politics, or of the pursuit of economic objectives). If this were true, it
would be wholly appropriate for economists and political theorists to look on
the problems of transition to peace as essentially mechanical or procedural---as
indeed they do, treating them as logistic corollaries of the settlement of
national conflicts of interest. If this were true, there would be no real
substance to the difficulties of transition. For it is evident that even in
today's world there exist no conceivable conflict of interest, real or
imaginary, between nations or between social forces within nations, that cannot
be resolved without recourse to war--if such resolution were assigned a priority
of social value. And if this were true, the economic analyses and disarmament
proposals we have referred to, plausible and well conceived as they may be,
would not inspire, as they do, an inescapable sense of indirection.
The point is that the cliche is not true, and the
problems of transition are indeed substantive rather than merely procedural.
Although was is "used" as an instrument of national and social policy, the fact
that a society is organized for any degree of readiness for war supersedes its
political and economic structure. War itself is the basic social system, within
which other secondary modes of social organization conflict or conspire. It is
the system which has governed most human societies of record, as it is
today.
Once this is correctly understood, the true
magnitude of the problems entailed in a transition to peace---itself a social
system, but without precedent except in a few simple preindustrial
societies---becomes apparent. At the same time, some of the puzzling superficial
contradictions of modern societies can then be readily rationalized. The
"unnecessary" size and power of the world war industry; the preeminence of the
military establishment in every society, whether open or concealed; the
exemption of military or paramilitary institutions from the accepted social and
legal standards of behavior required elsewhere in the society; the successful
operation of the armed forces and the armaments producers entirely outside the
framework of each nation's economic ground rules: these and other ambiquities
closely associated with the relationship of war to society are easily clarified,
once the priority of war-making potential as the principal structuring force in
society is accepted. Economic systems, political philosophies, and corpora jures
serve and extend the war system, not vice versa.
It must be emphasized that the precedence of a
society's war-making potential over its other characteristics is not the result
of the "threat" presumed to exist at any one time from other societies. This is
the reverse of the basic situation; "threath" against the "national interest"
are usually created or accelerated to meet the changing needs of the war system.
Only in comparatively recent times has it been considered politically expedient
to euphemize war budgets as "defense" requirements. The necessity for
governments to dis- tinguish between "aggression" (bad) and "defense" (good) has
been a by-product of rising literacy and rapid communication. The distinction is
tactical only, a concession to the growing inadequacy of ancient war-organizing
political rationales.
Wars are not "caused" by international conflicts of
interest. Proper logical sequence would make it more often accurate to say that
war-making societies require---and thus bring about---such conflicts. The
capacity of a nation to make war expresses the greatest social power it can
exercise; war-making, active or contemplated, is a matter of life and death on
the greatest scale subject to social control. It should therefore hardly be
surprising that the military institutions in each society claim its highest
priorities.
We find further that most of the confusion
surrounding the myth that war-making is a tool of state policy stems from a
general misapprehension of the functions of war. In general, these are conceived
as: to defend a nation from military attack by another, or to deter such an
attack; to defend or advance a "national interest"--economic, political,
idealogical; to maintain or in- crease a nation's military power for its own
sake. These are the visible, or ostensible, functions of war. If there were no
others, the importance of the war establishment in each society might in fact
decline to the subordinate level it is believed to occupy. And the elimination
of war would indeed be the procedural matter that the disarmament scenarios
suggest.
But there are other, broader, more profoundly felt
functions of war in modern societies. It is these invisivle, or implied,
functions that maintain war-readiness as the dominant force in our societies.
And it is the unwillingness or inability of the writers of disarmament scenarios
and reconversion plans to take them into account that has so reduced the
usefulness of their work, and that has made it seem unrelated to the world we
know.
SECTION 5 - THE FUNCTIONS OF WAR
As we have indicated, the preeminence of the
concept of war as the principal organizing force in most societies has been
insufficiently appreciated. This is also true of its extensive effects
throughout the many nonmilitary activities of society. These effects are less
apparent in complex industrial socie- ties like our own than in primitive
cultures, the activities of which can be more easily and fully comprehended.
We propose in this section to examine these
nonmilitary, implied, and usually invisible functions of war, to the extent that
they bear on the problems of transition to peace for our society. The military,
or ostensible, function of the war system requires no elaboration; it serves
simply to defend or advance the "national interest" by means of organized
violence. It is often necessary for a national military establishment to create
a need for its unique powers--to maintain the franchise, so to speak. And a
healthy military apparatus requires "exercise," by whatever rationale seems
expedient, to prevent its atrophy.
The nonmilitary functions of the war system are
more basic. They exist not merely to justify themselves but to serve broader
social purposes. If and when war is eliminated, the military functions it has
served will end with it. But its nonmilitary functions will not. It is
essential, therefore, that we understand their significance before we can
reasonably expect to evaluate whatever institutions may be proposed to replace
them.
ECONOMIC
The production of weapons of mass destruction has
always been associated with economic "waste." The term is pejorative, since it
implies a failure of function. But no human activity can properly be considered
wasteful if it achieves its contextual objective. The phrase "wasteful but
necessary," applied not only to war expenditures but to most of the
"unproductive" commercial activities of our society, is a contradiction in
terms. "...The attacks that have since the time of Samuel's criticism of King
Saul been leveled against military expenditures as waste may well have concealed
or misunderstood the point that some kinds of waste may have a larger social
utility."
In the case of military "waste," there is indeed a
larger social utility. It derives from the fact that the "wastefulness" of war
production is exercised entirely outside the framework of the economy of supply
and demand. As such, it provides the only critically large segment of the total
economy that is subject to complete and arbitrary central control. If modern
industrial societies can be defined as those which have developed the capacity
to produce more than is required for their economic survival (regardless of the
equities of distribution of goods within them), military spending can be said to
furnish the only balance wheel with sufficient inertia to stabilize the advance
of their economies. The fact that war is "wasteful" is what enables it to serve
this function. And the faster the economy advances, the heavier this balance
wheel must be.
This function is often viewed, oversimply, as a
device for the control of surpluses. One writer on the subject puts it this way:
"Why is war so wonderful? Because it creates artificial demand...the only kind
of artificial demand, moreover, that does not raise any political issues: war,
and only war, solves the problem of inventory." The reference here is to
shooting war, but it applies equally to the general war economy as well. "It is
generally agreed," concludes, more cautiously, the report of a panel set up by
the U.S. Arms Control and Disarmament Agency, "that the greatly expanded public
sector since World War II, resulting from heavy defense expenditures, has
provided additional protection against depressions, since this sector is not
responsive to con- traction in the private sector and has provided a sort of
buffer or balance wheel in the economy."
The principal economic function of war, in our
view, is that it provides just such a flywheel. It is not to be confused in
function with the various forms of fiscal control, none of which directly
engages vast numbers of control, none of which directly engages vast numbers of
men and units of production. It is not to be confused with massive government
expenditures in social welfare programs; once initiated, such programs normally
become integral parts of the general economy and are no longer subject to
arbitrary control.
But even in the context of the general civilian
economy war cannot be considered wholly "wasteful." Without a long-established
war economy, and without its frequent eruption into large-scale shooting war,
most of the major industrial advances known to history, beginning with the
development of iron, could never have taken place. Weapons technology structures
the economy. According to the writer cited above, "Nothing is more ironic or
revealing about our society than the fact that hugely destructive war is a very
progressive force in it. ... War production is progressive because it is
production that would not otherwise have taken place. (It is not so widely
appreciated, for example, that the civilian standard of living rose during World
War II.)" This is not "ironic or revealing," but essentially a simple statement
of fact.
It should also be noted that the war production has
a dependably stimulating effect outside itself. Far from constituting a
"wasteful" drain on the economy, war spending, considered pragmatically, has
been a consistently positive factor in the rise of gross national product and of
individual productivity. A former Secretary of the Army has carefully phrased it
for public consumption thus: "If there is, as I suspect there is, a direct
relation between the stimulus of large defense spending and a substantially
increased rate of growth of gross national product, it quite simply follows that
defense spending per se might be countenanced on economic grounds alone
[emphasis added] as a stimulator of the national metabolism." Actually, the
fundamental nonmilitary utility of war in the economy is far more widely
acknowledged than the scarcity of such affirmations as tha quoted above would
suggest.
But negatively phrased public recognitions of the
importance of war to the general economy abound. The most familiar example is
the effect of "peace threats" on the stock market, e.g., "Wall Street was shaken
yesterday by news of an apparent peace feeler from North Vietnam, but swiftly
recovered its com- posure after about an hour of sometimes indiscriminate
selling." Savings banks solicit deposits with similar cautionary slogans, e.g.,
"If peace breaks out, will you be ready for it?" A more subtle case in point was
the recent refusal of the Department of Defense to permit the West German
government to substitute nonmilitary goods for unwanted armaments in its
purchase commitments from the United States; the decisive consideration was that
the German purchases should not affect the general (nonmilitary) economy. Other
incidental examples are to be found in the pressures broght to bear on the
Department when it announces plans to close down an obsolete facility (as a
"wasteful" form of "waste"). and in the usual coordination of stepped-up
mililtary activities (as in Vietnam in 1965) with dangerously rising
unemployment rates.
Although we do not imply that a substitute for war
in the economy cannot be devised, no combination of techniques for controlling
employment, production, and consumption has yet been tested that can remotely
compare to it in effectiveness. It is, and has been, the essential economic
stabilizer of modern societies.
POLITICAL
The political functions of war have been up to now
even more critical to social stability. It is not surprising, nevertheless, that
discussions of economic conversion for peace tend to fall silent on the matter
of political implementation, and that disarmament scenarios, often sophisticated
in their weighing of international political factors, tend to disregard the
political functions of the war system withing individual societies.
These functions are essentially organizational.
First of all, the existence of a society as a political "nation" requires as
part of its definition an attitude of relationship toward other "nations." This
is what we usually call a foreign policy. But a nation's foreign policy can have
no substance if it lacks the means of enforcing its attitude toward other
nations. It can do this in a credible manner only if it implies the threat of
maximum political organization for this purpose--which is to say that it is
organized to some degree for war. War, then, as we have defined it to include
all national activities that recognize the possibility of armed conflict, is
itself the defining ele- ment of any nation's existence vis-a-vis any other
nation. Since it is historically axiomatic that the existence of any form of
weaponry insures its use, we have used the work "peace" as virtually synonymous
with disarmament. By the same token, "war" is virtually synonymous with
nationhood. The elimination of war implies the inevitable elimination of
national sovereignty and the traditional nation-state.
The war system not only has been essential to the
existence of nations as independent political entities, but has been equally
indispensable to their stable internal political structure. Without it, no
government has ever been able to obtain acquiescence in its "legitimacy," or
right to rule its society. The possibility of war provides the sense of external
necessity without which nor government can long remain in power. The historical
record reveals one instance after another where the failure of a regime to
maintain the credibility of a war threat led to its dissolution, by the forces
of private interest, or reactions to social injustice, or of other
disintegrative elements. The organization of a society for the possibility of
war is its principal political stabilizer. It is ironic that this primary
function of war has been generally recognized by historians only where it has
been expressly acknowledged--in the pirate societies of the great
conquerors.
The basic authority of a modern state over its
people resides in its war powers. (There is, in fact, good reason to believe
that codified law had its origins in the rules of conduct established by
military victors for dealing with the defeated enemy, which were later adapted
to apply to all subject populations.) On a day-to-day basis, it is represented
by the institution of police, armed organizations charged expressly with dealing
with "internal enemies" in a military manner. Like the conventional "external"
military, the police are also substantially exempt from many civilian legal
restraints on their social behavior. In some countries, the artificial
distinction between police and other military forces does not exist. On the
long-term basis, a government's emergency war powers -- inherent in the
structure of even the most libertarian of nations -- define the most significant
aspect of the relation between state and citizen.
In advanced modern democratic societies, the war
system has provided political leaders with another political-economic function
of increasing importance: it has served as the last great safeguard against the
elimination of necessary social classes. As economic productivity increases to a
level further and further above that of minimum subsistence, it becomes more and
more difficult for a society to maintain distribution patterns insuring the
existence of "hewers of wood and drawers of water". The further progress of
auto- mation can be expected to differentiate still more sharply between
"superior" workers and what Ricardo called "menials," while simultaneously
aggravating the problem of maintaining an unskilled labor supply.
The arbitrary nature of war expenditures and of
other military activities make them ideally suited to control these essential
class relationships. Obviously, if the war system were to be discarded, new
political machinery would be needed at once to serve this vital subfunction.
Until it is developed, the continuance of the war system must be assured, if for
no other reason, among others, than to preserve whatever quality and degree of
poverty a society requires as an incentive, as well as to maintain the stability
of its internal organization of power.
SOCIOLOGICAL
Under this heading, we will examine a nexus of
functions served by the war system that affect human behavior in society. In
general, they are broader in application and less susceptible to direct
observation than the economic and political factors previously considered.
The most obvious of these functions is the
time-honored use of military institutions to provide antisocial elements with an
acceptable role in the social structure. The disintegrative, unstable social
movements loosely described as "fascist" have traditionally taken root in
societies that have lacked adequate military or paramilitary outlets to meet the
needs of these elements. This function has been critical in periods of rapid
change. The danger signals are easy to recognize, even though the stigmata bear
different names at different times. The current euphemistic cliches--"juvenile
delinquency" and "alienation" -- have had their counterparts in every age. In
earlier days these conditions were dealt with directly by the military without
the complications of due process, usually through press gangs or outright
enslavement. But it is not hard to visualize, for example, the degree of social
disruption that might have taken place in the United States during the last two
decades if the problem of the socially disaffected of the post-World War II
period had been foreseen and effectively met. The younger, and more dangerous,
of these hostile social groupings have been kept under control by the Selective
Service System.
This system and its analogues elsewhere furnish
remarkably clear examples of disguised military utility. Informed persons in
this country have never accepted the official rationale for a peacetime
draft--military necessity, preparedness, etc. --as worthy of serious
consideration. But what has gained credence among thoughtful men is the rarely
voiced, less easily refuted, proposition that the institution of military
service has a "patriotic" priority in our society that must be maintained for
its own sake. Ironically, the simplistic official justification for selective
service comes closer to the mark, once the non-military functions of military
institutions are understood. As a control device over the hostile, nihilistic,
and potentially unsettling elements of a society in transition, the draft can
again be defended, and quite convincingly, as a "military" necessity.
Nor can it be considered a coincidence that overt
military activity, and thus the level of draft calls, tend to follow the major
fluctuations in the unemployment rate in the lower age groups. This rate, in
turn, is a timetested herald of social discontent. It must be noted also that
the armed forces in every civilization have provided the principal
state-supported haven for what we now call the "unemployable." The typical
European standing army (of fifty years ago) consisted of "...troops unfit for
employment in commerce, industry, or agriculture, led by officers unfit to
practice any legitimate profession or to conduct a business enterprise." This is
still largely true, if less apparent. In a sense, this function of the military
as the custodian of the economically or cuturally deprived was the forerunner of
most contemporary civilian social-welfare programs, from the W.P.A. to various
forms of "socialized" medicine and social security. It is interesting that
liberal sociologists currently proposing to use the Selective Service System as
a medium of cultural upgrading of the poor consider this a novel application of
military practice.
Although it cannot be said absolutely that such
critical measures of social control as the draft require a military rationale,
no modern society has yet been willing to risk experimentation with any other
kind. Even during such periods of comparatively simple social crisis as the
so-called Great Depression of the 1930s, it was deemed prudent by the government
to invest minor make-work projects, like the "Civilian" Conservation Corps, with
a military character, and to place the more ambitious National Recovery
Administration under the direction of a professional army officer at its
inception. Today, at least one small Northern European country, plagued with
uncontrollable unrest among its "alienated youth," is considering the expansion
of its armed forces, despite the problem of making credible the expansion of a
non-existent external threat.
Sporadic efforts have been made to promote general
recognition of broad national values free of military connotation, but they have
been ineffective. For example, to enlist public support of even such modest
programs of social adjustment as "fighting inflation" or "maintaining physical
fitness" it has been necessary for the government to utilize a patriotic (i.e.
military) incentive. It sells "defense" bonds and it equates health with
military preparedness. This is not surprising; since the concept of "nationhood"
implies readiness for war, a "national" program must do likewise.
In general, the war system provides the basic
motivation for primary social organization. In so doing, it reflects on the
societal level the incentives of individual human behavior. The most important
of these, for social purposes, is the individual psychological rationale for
allegiance to a society and its values. Allegiance requires a cause; a cause
requires an enemy. This much is obvious; the critical point is that the enemy
that defines the cause must seem genuinely formidable. Roughly speaking, the
presumed power of the "enemy" sufficient to warrant an individual sense of
allegiance to a society must be proportionate to the size and complexity of the
society. Today, of course, that power must be one of unprecedented magnitude and
frightfulness.
It follows, from the patterns of human behavior,
that the credibility of a social "enemy" demands similarly a readiness of
response in proportion to its menace. In a broad social context, "an eye for an
eye" still characterizes the only acceptable attitude toward a presumed threat
of aggression, despite con- trary religious and moral precepts governing
personal conduct. The remoteness of personal decision from social consequence in
a modern society makes it easy for its members to maintain this attitude without
being aware of it. A recent example is the war in Vietnam; a less recent one was
the bombing of Hiroshima and Nagasaki. In each case, the extent and
gratuitousness of the slaughter were abstracted into political formulae by most
Americans, once the proposition that the victims were "enemies" was established.
The war system makes such an abstracted response possible in nonmilitary
contexts as well. A conventional example of this mechanism is the inability of
most people to connect, let us say, the starvation of millions in India with
their own past conscious political decision-making. Yet the sequential logic
linking a decision to res- trict grain production in America with an eventual
famine in Asia is obvious, unambiguous, and unconcealed.
What gives the war system its preeminent role in
social organization, as elsewhere, is its unmatched authority over life and
death. It must be emphasized again that the war system is not a mere social
extension of the presumed need for individual human violence, but itself in turn
serves to rationalize most nonmilitary killing. It also provides the precedent
for the collective willingness of members of a society to pay a blood price for
institutions far less central to social organization that war. To take a handy
example..."rather than accept speed limits of twenty miles an hour we prefer to
let automobiles kill forty thousand people a year." A Rand analyst puts it in
more general terms and less rhetorically: "I am sure that there is, in effect, a
desirable level of automobile accidents---desirable, that is, from a broad point
of view; in the sense that it is a necessary concomitant of things of greater
value to society." The point may seem too obvious for iteration, but it is
essential to an understanding of the important motivational function of war as a
model for collective sacrifice.
A brief look at some defunct premodern societies is
instructive. One of the most noteworthy features common to the larger, more
complex, and more successful of ancient civilizations was their widespread use
of the blood sacrifice. If one were to limit consideratin to those cultures
whose regional hegemony was so complete that the prospect of "war" had become
virtually inconceivable ---as was the case with several of the great
pre-Columbian societies of the Western Hemisphere---it would be found that some
form of ritual killing occupied a position of paramount social importance in
each. Invariably, the ritual was invested with mythic or religious significance;
as will all religious and totemic practice, however, the ritual masked a broader
and more important social function.
In these societies, the blood sacrifice served the
purpose of maintaining a vestigial "earnest" of the society's capability and
willingness to make war-- i.e., kill and be killed---in the event that some
mystical--i.e., unforeseen --circumstance were to give rise to the possibility.
That the "earnest" was not an adequate substitute for genuine military
organization when the unthinkable enemy, such as the Spanish conquistadores,
actually appeared on the scene in no way negates the function of the ritual. It
was primarily, if not exclusively, a symbolic reminder that war had once been
the central organizing force of the society, and that this condition might
recur.
It does not follow that a transition to total peace
in modern societies would require the use of this model, even in less "barbaric"
guise. But the historical analogy serves as a reminder that a viable substitute
for war as a social system cannot be a mere symbolic charade. It must involve
risk of real personal destruction, and on a scale consistent with the size and
complexity of modern social systems. Credibility is the key. Whether the
substitute is ritual in nature or functionally substantive, unless it provides a
believable life- and-death threat it will not serve the socially organizing
function of war.
The existence of an accepted external menace, then,
is essential to social cohesiveness as well as to the acceptance of political
authority. The menace must be believable, it must be of a magnitude consistent
with the complexity of the society threatened, and it must appear, at least, to
affect the entire society.
ECOLOGICAL
Men, like all other animals, is subject to the
continuing process of adapting to the limitations of his environment. But the
principal mechanism he has utilized for this purpose is unique among living
creatures. To forestall the inevitable historical cycles of inadequate food
supply, post-Neolithic man destroys surplus members of his own species by
organized warfare.
Ethologists have often observed that the organized
slaughter of members of their own species is virtually unknown among other
animals. Man's special propensity to kill his own kind (shared to a limited
degree with rats) may be attributed to his inability to adapt anachronistic
patterns of survival (like primitive hunting) to his development of
"civilizations" in which these patterns cannot be effectively sublimated. It may
be attributed to other causes that have been suggested, such as a maladapted
"territorial instinct," etc. Nevertheless, it exists and its social expression
in war constitutes a biological control of his relationship to his natural
environment that is peculiar to man alone.
War has served to help assure the survival of the
human species. But as an evolutionary device to improve it, war is almost
unbelievably inefficient. With few exceptions, the selective processes of other
living creatures promote both specific survival and genetic improvement. When a
conventionally adaptive animal faces one of its periodic crises of
insufficiency, it is the "inferior" members of the species that normally
disappear. An animal's social response to such a crisis may take the form of a
mass migration, during which the weak fall by the wayside. Or it may follow the
dramatic and more efficient pattern of lemming societies, in which the weaker
members voluntarily disperse, leaving available food supplies for the stronger.
In either case, the strong survive and the weak fall. In human societies, those
who fight and die in wars for survival are in general its biologically stronger
members. This is natural selection in reverse.
The regressive genetic effort of war has been often
noted and equally often deplored, even when it confuses biological and cultural
factors. The disproportionate loss of the biologically stronger remains inherent
in traditional warfare. It serves to underscore the fact that survival of the
species, rather than its improvement, is the fundamental purpose of natural
selection, if it can be said to have a purpose, just as it is the basic premise
of this study.
But as the polemologist Gaston Bouthoul has pointed
out, other institutions that were developed to serve this ecological function
have proved even less satisfactory. (They include such established forms as
these: infanticide, practiced chiefly in ancient and primitive societies; sexual
mutilation; monasticism; forced emigration; extensive capital punishment, as in
old China and eighteenth-century England; and other similar, usually localized,
practices.)
Man's ability to increase his productivity of the
essentials of physical life suggests that the need for protection against
cyclical famine may be nearly obsolete. It has thus tended to reduce the
apparent importance of the basic ecological function of war, which is generally
disregarded by peace theorists. Two aspects of its remain especially relevant,
however. The first is obvious: current rates of population growth, compounded by
environmental threat to chemical and other contaminants, may well bring about a
new crisis of insufficiency. If so, it is likely to be one of unprecedented
global magnitude, not merely regional or temporary. Conventional methods of
warfare would almost surely prove inadequate, in this event, to reduce the
consuming population to a level consistent with survival of the species.
The second relevant factor is the efficiency of
modern methods of mass destruction. Even if their use is not required to meet a
world population crisis, they offer, perhaps paradoxically, the first
opportunity in the history of man to halt the regressive genetic effects of
natural selection by war. Nuclear weapons are indiscriminate. Their application
would bring to an end the disproportionate destruction of the physically
stronger members of the species (the "warriors") in periods of war. Whether this
prospect of genetic gain would offset the unfavorable mutations anticipated from
postnuclear radioactivity we have not yet determined. What gives the question a
bearing on our study is the possibility that the determination may yet have to
be made.
Another secondary ecological trend bearing on
projected population growth is the regressive effect of certain medical
advances. Pestilence, for example, is no longer an important factor in
population control. The problem of increased life expectancy has been
aggravated. These advances also pose a potentially more sinister problem, in
that undesirable genetic traits that were formerly self-liquidating are now
medically maintained. Many diseases that were once fatal at preprocreational ags
are now cured; the effect of this development is to perpetuate undesirable
susceptibilities and mutations. It seems clear that a new quasi-eugenic function
of war is now in process of formation that will have to be taken into account in
any transition plan. For the time being, the Department of Defense appears to
have recognized such factors, as has been demonstrated by the planning under way
by the Rand Corporation to cope with the breakdown in the ecological balance
anticipated after a thermonuclear war. The Department has also begun to
stockpile birds, for example, against the expected proliferation of
radiation-resistant insects, etc.
CULTURAL AND SCIENTIFIC
The declared order of values in modern societies
gives a high place to the so-called "creative" activities, and an even higher
one to those associated with the advance of scientific knowledge. Widely held
social values can be translated into political equivalents, which in turn may
bear on the nature of a transition to peace. The attitudes of those who hold
these values must be taken into account in the planning of the transition. The
dependence, therefore, of cultural and scientific achievement on the war system
would be an important consideration in a transition plan even is such
achievement had no inherently necessary social function.
Of all the countless dichotomies invented by
scholars to account for the major differences in art styles and cycles, only one
has been consistently unambiguous in its application to a variety of forms and
cultures. However it may be verbalized, the basic distinction is this: Is the
work war-oriented or is it not? Among primitive peoples, the war dance is the
most important art form. Elsewhere, literature, music, painting, sculpture, and
architecture that has won lasting acceptance has invariably dealt with a theme
of war, expressly or implicitly, and has expressed the centricity of war to
society. The war in question may be national conflict, as in Shakespeare plays,
Beethoven's music, or Goya's paintings, or it may be reflected in the form of
religious, social, or moral struggle, as in the work of Dante, Rembrandt, and
Bach. Art that cannot be classified as war-oriented is usually described as
"sterile," "decadent," and so on. Application of the "war standard" to works of
art may often leave room for debate in individual cases, but there is no
question of its role as the fundamental determinant of cultural values.
Aesthetic and moral standards have a common anthropological origin, in the
exaltation of bravery, the willingness to kill and risk death in tribal
warfare.
It is also instructive to note that the character
of a society's culture has borne a close relationship to its war-making
potential, in the context of its times. It is no accident that the current
"cultural explosion" in the United States is taking place during an era marked
by an unusually rapid advance in weaponry. This relationship is more generally
recognized than the literature on the subject would suggest. For example, many
artists and writers are now beginning to express concern over the limited
creative options they envisage in the warless world they think, or hope, may be
soon upon us. They are currently preparing for this possibility by unprecedented
experimentation with meaningless forms; their interest in recent years has been
increasingly engaged by the abstract pattern, the gratuitous emotin, the random
happening, and the unrelated sequence.
The relationshp of war to scientific research and
discovery is more explicit. War is the principal motivational force for the
development of science at every level, from the abstractly conceptual to the
narrowly technological. Modern society places a high value on "pure" science,
but it is historically inescapable that all the significant discoveries that
have been made about the natural world have been inspired by the real or
imaginary military necessities of their epochs. The consequences of the
discoveries have indeed gone far afield, but war has always provided the basic
incentive.
Beginning with the development of iron and steel,
and proceeding through the discoveries of the laws of motion and thermodynamics
to the age of the atomic particle, the synthetic polymer, and the space capsure,
no important scientific advance has not been at least indirectly initiated by an
implicit requirement of weaponry. More prosaic examples include the transistor
radio (an outgrowth of military communications requirements), the assembly line
(from Civil War firearms needs), the steel-frame building (from the steel
battleship), the canal lock, and so on. A typical adaptation can be seen in a
device as modest as the common lawnmower; it developed from the revolving scythe
devised by Leonardo da Vinci to precede a horse-powered vehicle into enemy
ranks.
The most direct relationship can be found in
medical technology. For example, a giant "walking machine," and amplifier of
body motions invented for military use in difficult terrain, is now making it
possible for many previously con- fined to wheelchairs to walk. The Vietnam war
alone has led to spectacular improvements in amputation procedures,
blood-handling techniques, and surgical logistics. It has stimulated new
large-scale research on malaria and other typical parasite diseases; it is hard
to estimate how long this t? Amoould otherwise have been delayed, despite its
enormous nonmilitary importance to nearly half the world's population.
OTHER
We have elected to omit from our discussion of the
nonmilitary functions of war those we do not consider critical to a transition
program. This is not to say they are unimportant, however, but only that they
appear to present no special problems for the organization of a peace-oriented
social system. They include the following:
-
War as a general social release. This is a
psychosocial function, serving the same purpose for a society as do the holiday,
the celebration, and the orgy for the individual---the release and
redistribution of undifferentiated tensions. War provides for the periodic
necessary readjustment of standards of social behavior (the "moral climate") and
for the dissipation of general boredom, one of the most consistently undervalued
and unrecognized of social phenomena.
-
War as a generational stabilizer. This
psychological function, served by other behavior patterns in other animals,
enables the physically deteriorating older generation to maintain its control of
the younger, destroying it if necessary.
-
War as an idealogical clarifier. The
dualism that characterized the traditional dialectic of all branches of
philosophy and of stable political relationships stems from war as the prototype
of conflict. Except for secondary considerations, there cannot be, to put it as
simply as possible, more than two sides to a question because there cannot be
more than two sides to a war.
-
War as the basis for the international
understanding. Before the development of modern communications, the
strategic requirements of war provided the only substantial incentive for the
enrichment of one national culture with the achievements of another. Altough
this is still the case in many international relationships, the function is
obsolescent.
We have also forgone extended characterization of
those functions we assume to be widely and explicitly recognized. An obvious
example is the rold of war as controller of the quality and degree of
unemployment. This is more than an economic and political subfunction; its
sociological, cultural, and ecological aspects are also important, although
often teleonomic. But none affect the general problem of substitution. The same
is true of certain other functions; those we have included are sufficient to
define the scope of the problem.
SECTION 6 - SUBSTITUTES FOR THE FUNCTIONS OF
WAR
By now it should be clear that the most detailed
and comprehensive master plan for a transition to world peace will remain
academic if it fails to deal forthrightly with the problem of the critical
nonmilitary functions of war. The social needs they serve are essential; if the
war system no longer exists to meet them, substitute institutions will have to
be established for the purpose. These surrogates must be "realistic," which is
to say of a scope and nature that can be conceived and implemented in the
context of present-day social capabilities. This is not the truism it may appear
to be; the requirements of radical social change often reveal the distinction
between a most conservative projection and a wildly utopian scheme to be fine
indeed.
In this section we will consider some possible
substitutes for these functions. Only in rare instances have they been put forth
for the purposes which concern us here, but we see no reason to limit ourselves
to proposals that address themselves explicitly to the problem as we have
outlined it. We will disregard the ostensible, or military, functions of war; it
is a premise of this study that the transition to peace implies absolutely that
they will no longer exist in any relevant sense. We will also disregard the
noncritical functions exemplified at the end of the preceding section.
ECONOMIC
Economic surrogates for war must meet two principal
criteria. They must be "wasteful," in the common sense of the word, and they
must operate outside the normal supply-demand system. A corollary that should be
obvious is that the magnitude of the waste must be sufficient to meet the needs
of a particular society. An economy as advanced and complex as our own requires
the planned average annual destructoin of not less than 10 percent of gross
national product if it is effectively to fulfill its stabilizing function. When
the mass of a balance wheel is inadequate to the power it is intended to
control, its effect can be self-defeating, as with a runaway locomotive. The
analogy, though crude, is especially apt for the American economy, as our record
of cyclical depressions shows. All have taken place during periods of grossly
inadequate military spending.
Those few economic conversion programs which by
implication acknowledge the nonmilitary economic function of war (at least to
some extent) tend to assume that so-called social-welfare expenditures will fill
the vacuum created by the disappearance of military spending. When one considers
the backlog of un- finished business---proposed but still unexecuted---in this
field, the assumption seems plausible. Let us examine briefly the following
list, which is more or less typical of general social welfare programs.
-
HEALTH. Drastic expansion of medical
research, education, and training facilities; hospital and clinic construction;
the general objective of complete government-guaranteed health care for all, at
a level consistent with current developments in medical technology.
-
EDUCATION. The equivalent of the foregoing
in teacher training; schools and libraries; the drastic upgrading of standards,
with the general objective of making available for all an attainable educational
goal equivalent to what is now considered a professional degree.
-
HOUSING. Clean, comfortable, safe, and
spacious living space for all, at the level now enjoyed by about 15 percent of
the population in this country (less in most others).
-
TRANSPORTATION. The establishment of a
system of mass public transportation making it possible for all to travel to and
from areas of work and recreation quickly, comfortably, and conveniently, and to
travel privately for pleasure rather than necessity.
-
PHYSICAL ENVIRONMENT. The development and
protection of water supplies, forests, parks, and other natural resources; the
elimination of chemical and bacterial contaminants from air, water, and soil.
-
POVERTY. The genuine elimination of
poverty, defined by a standard consistent with current economic productivity, by
means of a guaranteed annual income or whatever system of distribution will best
assure its achievement.
This is only a sampler of the more obvious domestic
social welfare items, and we have listed it in a deliberately broad, perhaps
extravagant, manner. In the past, such a vague and ambitious-sounding "program"
would have been dismissed out of hand, without serious consideration; it would
clearly have been, prima facie, far too costly, quite apart from its political
implications. Our objective to it, on the other hand, could hardly be more
contradictory. As an economic substitute for war, it is inadequate because it
would be far too cheap.
If this seems paradoxical, it must be remembered
that up to now all proposed social-welfare expenditures have had to be measured
within the war economy, not as a replacement for it. The old slogan about a
battleship or an ICBM costing as much as x hospitals or y schools or z homes
takes on a very different meaning if there are to be more battleships or
ICBM's.
Since the list is general, we have elected to
forestall the tangential controversy that surrounds arbitraty cost projections
by offering no individual cost estimates. But the maximum program that could be
physically effected along the lines indicated could approach the established
level of military spending only for a limited time--in our opinion, subject to a
detailed cost-and-feasibility analysis, less than ten years. In this short
period, at this rate, the major goals of the program would have been achieved.
Its capital-investment phase would have been completed, and it would have
established a permanent comparatively modest level of annual operating
cost--within the framework of the general economy.
Here is the basic weakness of the sociel-welfare
surrogate. On the short-term basis, a maximum program of this sort could replace
a normal military spending program, provided it was designed, like the military
model, to be subject to arbitrary control. Public housing starts, for example,
or the development of modern medical centers might be accelerated or halted from
time to time, as the requirements of a stable economy might dictate. But on the
long-term basis, social-welfare spending, no matter how often redefined, would
necessarily become an integral, accepted part of the economy, of no more value
as a stabilizer than the automobile industry or old age and survivors'
insurance. Apart from whatever merit social-welfare programs are deemed to have
for their own sake, their function as a substitute for war in the economy would
thus be self-liquidating. They might serve, however, as expedients pending the
development of more durable substitute measures.
Another economic surrogate that has been proposed
is a series of giant "space research" programs. These have already demonstrated
their utility in more modest scale within the military economy. What has been
implied, although not yet expressly put forth, is the development of a
long-range sequence of space-research projects with largely unattainable goals.
This kind of program offers several advantages lacking in the social welfare
model. First, it is unlikely to phase itself out, regardless of the predictable
"surprises" science has in store for us: the universe is too big. In the event
some individual project unexpectedly succeeds there would be no dearth of
substitute problems. For example, if colonization of the moon proceeds on
schedule, it could then become "necessary" to establish a beachhead on Mars or
Jupiter, and so on. Second, it need be no more dependent on the general
supply-demand economy than its military prototype. Third, it lends itself
extraordinarily well to arbitrary control.
Space research can be viewed as the nearest modern
equivalent yet devised to the pyramid-building, and similar ritualistic
enterprises, of ancient societies. It is true that the scientific value of the
space program, even of what has already been accomplished, is substantial on its
own terms. But current programs are absurdly obviously disproportionate, in the
relationship of the knowledge sought to the expenditures committed. All but a
small fraction of the space budget, measured by the standards of comparable
scientific objectives, must be charged de facto to the military economy. Future
space research, projected as a war surrogate, would further research, projected
as a war surrogate, would further reduce the "scientific" rationale of its
budget to a minuscule percentage indeed. As a purely economic substitute for
war, therefore, extension of the space program warrants serious
consideraton.
In Section 3 we pointed out that certain
disarmament models, which we called conservative, postulated extremely expensive
and elaborate inspection systems. Would it be possible to extend and
institutionalize such systems to the point where they might serve as economic
surrogates for war spending? The organization of failsafe inspection machinery
could well be ritualized in a manner similar to that of established military
processes. "Inspection teams" might be very like weapons. Inflating the
inspection budget to military scale presents no difficulty. The appeal of this
kind of scheme lies in the comparative ease of transition between two parallel
systems.
The "elaborate inspection" surrogate is
fundamentally fallacious, however. Although it might be economically useful, as
well as politically necessary, during the disarmament transition, it would fail
as a substitute for the economic function of war for one simple reason.
Peace-keeping inspection is part of a war system, not of a peace system. It
implies the possibility of weapons maintenance or manufacture, which could not
exist in a world at peace as here defined. Massive inspection also implies
sanctions, and thus war-readiness.
The same fallacy is more obvious in plans to create
a patently useless "defense conversion" apparatus. The long-discredited proposal
to build "total" civil defense facilities is one example; another is the plan to
establish a giant antimissile missile complex (Nike-X, et al.). These programs,
of course, are economic rather than strategic. Nevertheless, they are not
substitutes for military spending but merely different forms of it.
A more sophisticated variant is the proposal to
establish the "Unarmed Forces" of the United States. This would conveniently
maintain the entire institutional military structure, redirecting it essentially
toward social-welfare activities on a global scale. It would be, in effect, a
giant military Peace Corps. There is nothing inherently unworkable about this
plan, and using the existing military system to effectuate its own demise is
both ingenious and convenient. But even on a greatly magnified world basis,
social-welfare expenditures must sooner or later reenter the atmosphere of the
normal economy. The practical transitional virtues of such a scheme would thus
be eventually negated by its inadequacy as a permanent economic stabilizer.
POLITICAL
The war system makes the stable government of
societies possible. It does this essentially by providing an external necessity
for a society to accept political rule. In so doing, it establishes the basis
for nationhood and the authority of government to control its constituents. What
other institution or combination of programs might serve these functions in its
place?
We have already pointed out that the end of the war
means the end of national sovereignty, and thus the end of nationhood as we know
it today. But this does not necessarily mean the end of nations in the
administrative sense, and internal political power will remain essential to a
stable society. The emerging "nations" of the peace epoch must continue to draw
political authority from some source.
A number of proposals have been made governing the
relations between nations after total disarmament; all are basically juridical
in nature. They contemplate institutions more or less like a World Court, or a
United Nations, but vested with real authority. They may or may not serve their
ostansible post-military purpose of settling internatinal disputes, but we need
not discuss that here. None would offer effective external pressure on a
peace-world nation to organize itself politically.
It might be argued that a well-armed international
police force, operating under the authority of such a supranational "court,"
could well serve the function of external enemy. This, however, would constitute
a military operation, like the inspection schemes mentioned, and, like them,
would be inconsistent with the premise of an end to the war system. It is
possible that a variant of the "Unarmed Forces" idea might be developed in such
a way that its "constructive" (i.e., social welfare) activities could be
combined with an economic "threat" of sufficient size and credibility to warrant
political organization. Would this kind of threat also be contradictory to our
basic premise?--that is, would it be inevitably military? Not necessarily, in
our view, but we are skeptical of its capacity to evoke credibility. Also, the
obvious destabilizing effect of any global social welfare surrogate on
politically necessary class relationships would create an entirely new set of
transition problems at least equal in magnitude.
Credibility, in fact, lies at the heart of the
problem of developing a political substitute for war. This is where the
space-race proposals, in many ways so well suited as economic substitutes for
war, fall short. The most ambitious and unrealistic space project cannot of
itself generate a believable external menace. It has been hotly argued that such
a menace would offer the "last, best hope of peace," etc., by uniting mankind
against the danger of destruction by "creatures" from other planets or from
outer space. Experiments have been proposed to test the credibility of an
out-of-our-world invasion threat; it is possible that a few of the more
difficult-to-explain "flying saucer" indicents of recent years were in fact
early experiments of this kind. If so, they could hardly have been judged
encouraging. We anticipate no difficulties in making a "need" for a giant super
space program credible for economic purposes, even were there not ample
precedent; extending it, for political purposes, to include features
unfortunately associated with science fiction would obviously be a more dubious
undertaking.
Nevertheless, an effective political substitute for
war would require "alternate enemies," some of which might seem equally
farfetched in the context of the current war system. It may be, for instance,
that gross pollution of the environment can eventually replace the possibility
of mass destruction by nuclear weapons as the principal apparent threat to the
survival of the species. Poisoning of the air, and of the principal sources of
food and water supply, is already well advanced, and at first glance would seem
promising in this respect; it constitutes a threat that can be dealt with only
through social organization and political power. But from present indications it
will be a generation to a generation and a half before environmental pollution,
however severe, will be sufficiently menacing, on a global scale, to offer a
possible basis for a solution.
It is true that the rate of pollution could be
increased selectively for this purpose; in fact, the mere modifying of existing
programs for the deterrence of pollution could speed up the process enough to
make the threat credible much sooner. But the pollution problem has been so
widely publicized in recent years that it seems highly improbably that a program
of deliberate environ- mental poisoning could be implemented in a politically
acceptable manner.
However unlikely some of the possible alternate
enemies we have mentioned may seem, we must emphasize that one must be found, of
credible quality and magnitude, if a transition to peace is ever to come about
without social disintegration. It is more probably, in our judgement, that such
a threat will have to be invented, rather than developed from unknown
conditions. For this reason, we believe further speculation about its putative
nature ill-advised in this context. Since there is considerable doubt, in our
minds, that any viable political surrogate can be devised, we are reluctant to
compromise, by premature discussion, any possible option that may eventually lie
open to our government.
SOCIOLOGICAL
Of the many functions of war we have found
convenient to group together in this classification, two are critical. In a
world of peace, the continuing stability of society will require: 1) an
effective substitute for military institutions that can neutralize destabilizing
social elements and 2) a credible motivational surrogate for war that can insure
social cohesiveness. The first is an essential element of social control; the
second is the basic mechanism for adapting individual human drives to the needs
of society.
Most proposals that address themselves, explicitly
or otherwise, to the postwar problem of controlling the socially alienated turn
to some variant of the Peace Corps or the so-called Job Corps for a solution.
The socially disaffected, the economically unprepared, the psychologically
unconformable, the hard-core "delinquents," the incorrigible "subversives," and
the rest of the unemployable are seen as somehow transformed by the disciplines
of a service modeled on military precedent into more or less dedicated social
service workers. This presumption also informs the otherwise hardheaded
ratiocination of the "Unarmed Forces" plan.
The problem has been addressed, in the language of
popular sociology, by Secretary McNamara. "Even in our abundant societies, we
have reason enough to worry over the tensions that coil and tighten among
underprivileged young people, and finally flail out in delinquency and crime.
What are we to expect.. where mounting frustrations are likely to fester into
eruptions of violence and extremism?" In a seemingly unrelated passage, he
continues: "It seems to me that we could move toward remedying that inequity [of
the Selective Service System] by asking every young person in the United States
to give two years of service to his country--whether in one of the military
services, in the Peace Corps, or in some other volunteer developmental w? Amat
home or abroad. We could encourage other countries to do the same." Here, as
elsewhere throughout this significant speech, Mr.McNamara has focused,
indirectly but unmistakably, on one of the key issues bearing on a possible
transition to peace, and has later indicated, also indirectly, a rough approach
to its resolution, again phrased in the language of the current war system.
It seems cleara that Mr.McNamara and other
proponents of the peace-corps surrogate for this tar function lean heavily on
the success of the paramilitary Depression programs mentioned in the last
section. We find the precedent wholly inadequate in degree. Neither the lack of
relevant precedent, however, nor the dubious social welfare sentimentality
characterizing this approach warrant its rejection without careful study. It may
be viable --- provided, first, that the military origin of the Corps format be
effectively rendered out of its operational activity, and second, that the
transition from paramilitary activities to "developmental w? A" can be effected
without regard to the attitudes of the Corps personnel or to the "value" of the
work it is expected to perform.
Another possible surrogate for the control of
potential enemies of society is the reintroduction, in some form consistent with
modern technology and political processes, of slavery. Up to now, this has been
suggested only in fiction, notably in the works of Wells, Huxley, Orwell, and
others engaged in the imaginative anticipation of the sociology of the future.
But the fantasies projected in Brave New World and 1984 have seemed less and
less implausible over the years since their publication. The traditional
association of slavery with ancient preindustrial cultures should not blind us
to its adaptability to advanced forms of social organization, nor should its
equally traditional incompatibility with Western moral and economic values. It
is entirely possible that the development of a sophisticated form of slavery may
be an absolute prerequisite for social control in a world at peace. As a
practical matter, conversion of the code of military discipline to a euphemized
form of enslavement would entail surprisingly little revision; the logical first
stepmoould be the adoption of some form of "universal" military service.
When it comes to postulating a credible substitute
for war capable of directing human behavior patterns in behalf of social
organization, few options suggest themselves. Like its political function, the
motivational function of war requires the existence of a genuinely menacing
social enemy. The principal difference is that for purposes of motivating basic
allegiance, as distinct from accepting political authority, the "alternate
enemy" must imply a more immediate, tangible, and directly felt threat of
destruction. It must justify the need for taking and paying a "blood price" in
wide areas of human concern.
In this respect, the possible enemies noted earlier
would be insufficient. One exception might be the environmental-pollution model,
if the danger to society it posed was genuinely imminent. The fictive models
would have to carry the weight of extraordinary conviction, underscored with a
not inconsiderable actual sacrifice of life; the construction of an up-to-date
mythological or religious structure for this purpose would present difficulties
in our era, but must certainly be considered.
Games theorists have suggested, in other contexts,
the development of "blood games" for the effective control of individual
aggressive impulses. It is an ironic commentary on the current state of war and
peace studies that it was left not to scientists but to the makers of a
commercial film to develop a model for this notion, on the implausible level of
popular melodrama, as a ritualized manhunt. More realistically, such a ritual
might be socialized, in the manner of the Spanish Inquisition and the less
formal witch trials of other periods, for purposes of "social purification,"
"state security," or other rationale both acceptable and credible to postwar
societies. The feasibility of such an updated version of still another ancient
institution, though doubtful, is considerably less fanciful than the wishful
notion of many peace planners that a lasting condition of peace can be brought
about without the most painstaking examination of every possible surrogate for
the essential functions of war. What is involved here, in a sense, is the quest
for William Jame's "moral equivalent of war."
It is also possible that the two functions
considered under this heading may be jointly served, in the sense of
establishing the antisocial, for whom a control institution is needed, as the
"alternate enemy" needed to hold society together. The relentless and
irreversible advance of unemployability at all levels of society, and the
similar extension of generalized alienation from accepted values may make some
such program necessary even as an adjunct to the war system. As before, we will
not speculate on the specific forms this kind of program might take, except to
note that there is again ample precedent, in the treatment meted out to
disfavored, allegedly menacing, ethnic groups in certain societies during
certain historical periods.
ECOLOGICAL
Considering the shortcomings of war as a mechanism
of selective population control, it might appear that devising substitutes for
this function should be comparatively simple. Schematically this is so, but the
problem of timing the transition to a new ecological balancing device makes the
feasibility of substitution less certain.
It must be remembered that the limitation of war in
this function is entirely eugenic. War has not been genetically progressive. But
as a system of gross population control to preserve the species it cannot fairly
be faulted. And, as has been pointed out, the nature of war is itself in
transition. Current trends in warfare--the increased strategic bombing of
civilians and the greater mililtary importance now attached to the destruction
of sources of supply (as opposed to purely "military" bases and
personnel)---strongly suggest that a truly qualititative improvement is in the
making. Assuming the war system is to continue, it is more than probably that
the regressively selective quality of war will have been reversed, as its
victims become more genetically representative of their societies.
There is no question but that a universal
requirement that procreation be limited to the products of artificial
inseminatin would provide a fully adequate substitute control for population
levels. Such a reproductive system would, of course, have the added advantage of
being susceptible of direct eugenic management. Its predictable further
development---conception and embryonic growth taking place wholly under
laboratory conditions--would extend these controls to their logical conclusion.
The ecological function of war under these circumstances would not only be
superseded but surpassed in effectiveness.
The indicated intermediate step--total control of
conception with a variant of the ubiquitous "pill," via water supplies or
certain essential foodstuffs, offset by a controlled "antidote"---is already
under development. There oould appear to be no foreseeable need to revert to any
of the outmoded practices referred to in the previous section (infanticide,
etc.) as there might have been if the possibility of transition to peace had
arisen two generations ago.
The real question here, therefore, does not concern
the viability of this war substitute, but the political problems involved in
bringing it about. It cannot be established while the war system is still in
effect. The reason for this is simple: excess population is tar material. As
long as any society must comtemplate even a remote possibility ofwar, it must
maintain a maximum supportable population, even when so doing critically
aggravates an economic liability. This is paradoxical, in view of war's role in
reducing excess population, but it is readily understood. War controls the
general population level, but the ecological interest of any single society lies
in maintaining its hegemony vis-a-vis other societies. The obvious analogy can
be seen in any free-enterprise economy. Practices damaging to the society as a
whole--both competitive and monopolistic--are abetted by the conflicting
economic motives of individual capital interests. The obvious precedent can be
found in the seemingly irrational political difficulties which have blacked
universal adoption of simple birth-control methods. Nations desperately in need
of increasing unfavorable production-consumption ratios are nevertheless
unwilling to gamble their possible military requirements of twenty years hence
for this purpose. Unilateral population control, as practiced in ancient Japan
and in other isolated societies, is out of the question in today's world.
Since the eugenic solution cannot be achieved until
the transition to the peace system takes place, why not wait? One must qualify
the inclination to agree. As we noted earlier, a real possibility of an
unprecedented global crisis of insufficiency exists today, which the war system
may not be able to forestall. If this should come to pass before an agreed-upon
transition to peace were completed, the result might be irrevocably disastrous.
There is clearly no solution to this dilemma; it is a risk which must be taken.
But it tends to support the view that if a decision is made to elminate the war
system, it were better done sooner than later.
CULTURAL AND SCIENTIFIC
Strictly speaking, the function of war as the
determinant of cultural values and as the prime mover of scientific progress may
not be critical in a world without war. Our criterion for the basic nonmilitary
functions of war has been: Are they necessary to the survival and stability of
society? The absolute need for substitute cultural value-determinants and for
the continued advance of scientific knowledge is not established. We believe it
important, however, in behalf of those for whom these functions hold subjective
significance, that it be known what they can reasonably expect in culture and
science after a transition to peace.
So far as the creative arts are concerned, there is
no reason to believe they would disappear, but only that they would change in
charactermand relative social importance. The elimination of war would in due
course deprive them of their principal conative force, but it would necessarily
take some time for the transition, and perhaps for a generation thereafter,
themes of sociomoral conflict inspired by the war system would be increasingly
transferred to the idiom of purely personal sensibility. At the same time, a new
aesthetic oould have to develop. Whatever its name, form, or rationale, its
function would be to express, in language appropriate to the new period, the
once discredited philosophy that art exists for its own sake. This aesthetic
oould reject unequivocally the classic requirement of paramilitary conflict as
the substantive content of great art. The eventual effect of the peace-world
philosophy of art would be deomcratizing in the extreme, in the sense that a
generally acknowledged subjectivity of artistic standards would equalize their
new, content-free "values."
What may be expected to happen is that art would be
reassigned the role it once played in a few primitive peace-oriented social
systems. This was the functin of pure decoration, entertainment, or play,
entirely free of the burden of expressing the sociomoral values and conflicts of
a war-oriented society. It is interesting that the groundwork for such a
value-free aesthetic is already being laid today, in growing experimentation in
art without content, perhaps in anticipation of a world without conflict. A cult
has developed around a new kind of cultural determinism, which proposes that the
technological form of a cultural expression determines its values rather than
does its ostensibly meaningful content. Its clear implication is that there is
no "good" or "bad" art, only that which is appropriate to its (technological)
times and that which is not. Its cultural effect has been to promote
circumstantial constructions and unplanned expressions; it denies to art the
relevance of sequential logic. Its significance in this context is that it
provides a working model of one kind of value-free culture we might reasonably
anticipate in a world at peace.
So far as science is concerned, it might appear at
first glance that a giant space-research program, the most promising among the
proposed economic surrogates for war, might also serve as the basic stimulator
of scientific research. The lack of fundamental organized social conflict
inherent in space work, however, would rule it out as an adeguate motivational
substitute for war when applied to "pure" science. But it could no doubt sustain
the broad range of technological activity that a space budget of military
dimensions oould require. A similarly scaled social-welfare program could
provide a comparable inpetus to low-keyed technological advances, especially in
medicine, rationalized construction methods, educational psychology, etc. The
eugenic substitute for the ecological function of war oould also require
continuing research in certain areas of the life sciences.
Apart from these partial substitutes for war, it
must be kept in mind that the momentum given to scientific progress by the great
wars of the past century, and even more by the anticipation of World War III, is
intellectually and materially enormous. It is our finding that if the war system
were to end tomorrow this momentum is so great that the pursuit of scientific
knowledge could reasonably be expected to go forward without noticeable
diminution for perhaps two decades. It would then continue, at a progressively
decreasing tempo, for at least another two decades before the "bank account" of
today's unresolved problems would become exhausted. By the standards of the
questions we have learned to ask today, there would no longer be anything worth
knowing still unknown; we cannot conceive, by definition, of the scientific
questions to ask once those we can now comprehend are answered.
This leads unavoidably to another matter: the
intrinsic value of the unlimited search for knowledge. We of course offer no
independent value judgments here, but it is germane to point out that a
substantial minority of scientific opinion feels that search to be circumscribed
in any case. This opinion is itself a factor in considering the need for a
substitute for the scientific function of war. For the record, we must also take
note of the precedent that during long periods of human history, often covering
thousands of years, in which no intrinsic social value was assigned to
scientific progress, stable societies did survive and flourish. Although this
could not have been possible in the modern industrial world, we cannot be
certain it may not again be true in a future world at peace.
SECTION 7 - SUMMARY AND CONCLUSIONS
THE NATURE OF WAR
War is not, as is widely assumed, primarily an
instrument of polcy utilized by nations to extend or defend their expressed
political values or their economic interests. On the contrary, it is itself the
principal basis of organizatin on which all modern societies are constructed.
The common proximate cause of war is the apparent interference of one nation
with the aspirations of another. But at the root of all ostensible differences
of national interest lie the dynamic requirements of the war system itself for
periodic armed conflict. Readiness for war characterizes contemporary social
systems more broadly than their economic and political structures, which it
subsumes.
Economic analyses of the anticipated problems of
transition to peace have not recognized the broad preminence of war in the
definition of social systems. The same is true, with rare and only partial
exceptions, of model disarmament "scenarios." For this reason, the value of this
previous work is limited to the mechanical aspects of transition. Certain
features of these models may perhaps be applicable to a real situation of
conversion to peace; this till depend on their compatibility with a substantive,
rather than a procedural, peace plan. Such a plan can be developed only from the
premise of full understanding of the nature of the war system it proposes to
abolish, which in turn presupposes detailed comprehension of the functions the
war system performs for society. It will require the construction of a detailed
and feasible system of substitutes for those functions that are necessary to the
stability and survival of human societies.
THE FUNCTIONS OF WAR
The visible, military function of war requires no
elucidation; it is not only obvious but also irrelevant to a transition to the
condition of peace, in which it will by definition be superfluous. It is also
subsidiary in social significance to the implied, nonmilitary functions of war;
those critical to transition can be summarized in five principal groupings.
-
ECONOMIC. War has provided both ancient
and modern societies with a dependable system for stabilizing and controlling
national economies. No alternate method of control has yet been tested in a
complex modern economy that has shown itself remotely comparable in scope or
effectiveness.
-
POLITICAL. The permanent possibility of
war is the foundation for stable government; it supplies the basis for general
acceptance of political authority. It has enabled societies to maintain
necessary class distinctions, and it has ensured the subordination of the
citizen to the state, by virtue of the residual war powers inherent in the
concept of nationhood. No modern political ruling group has successfully
controlled its constituency after failing to sustain the continuing credibility
of an external threat of war.
-
SOCIOLOGICAL. War, through the medium of
military institutions, has uniquely served societies, throughout the course of
known history, as an indispensible controller of dangerous social dissidence and
destructive antisocial tendencies. As the most formidable of threats to life
itself, and as the only one susceptible to mitigation by social organization
alone, it has played another equally fundamental role: the war system has
provided the machinery through which the motivational forces governing human
behavior have been translated into binding social allegiance. It has thus
ensured the degree of social cohesion necessary to the viability of nations. No
other institution, or groups of institutions, in modern societies, has
successfully served these functions.
-
ECOLOGICAL. War has been the principal
evolutionary device for maintaining a satisfactory ecological balance between
gross human population and supplies available for its survival. It is unique to
the human species.
-
CULTURAL AND SCIENTIFIC. War-orientation
has determined the basic standards of value in the creative arts, and has
provided the fundamental motivational source of scientific and technological
progress. The concepts that the arts express values independent of their own
forms and that the successful pursuit of knowledge has intrinsic social value
have long been accepted in modern societies; the development of the arts and
sciences during this period has been corollary to the parallel development of
weaponry.
SUBSTITUTES FOR THE FUNCTIONS OF WAR:
CRITERIA
The foregoing functions of war are essential to the
survival of the social systems we know today. With two possible exceptions they
are also essential to any kind of stable social organization that might survive
in a warless world. Discussion of the ways and means of transition to such a
world are meaningless unless a)substitute institutions can be devised to fill
these functions, or b) it can reasonably be hypothecated that the loss or
partial loss of any one function need not destroy the viability of future
societies.
Such substitute institutions and hypotheses must
meet varying criteria. In general, they must be technically feasible,
politically acceptable, and potentially credible to the members of the societies
that adopt them. Specifically, they must be characterized as follows:
-
ECONOMIC. An acceptable economic surrogate
for the war system will require the expenditure of resources for completely
nonproductive purposes at a level comparable to that of the military
expenditures otherwise demanded by the size and complexity of each society. Such
a substitute system of apparent "waste" must be of a nature that will permit it
to remain independent of the normal supply-demand economy; it must be subject to
arbitrary political control.
-
POLITICAL. A viable political substitute
fir war must posit a generalized external menace to each society of a nature and
degree sufficient to require the organization and acceptance of political
authority.
-
SOCIOLOGICAL. First, in the permanent
absence of war, new institutions must be developed that will effectively control
the socially destructive seg- ments of societies. Second, for purposes of
adapting the physical and psychological dynamics of human behavior to the needs
of social organization, a credible substitute for war must generate an
omnipresent and readily understood fear of personal destruction. This fear must
be of a nature and degree sufficient to ensure adherence to societal values to
the full extent that they are acknowledged to transcend the value of individual
human life.
-
ECOLOGICAL. A substitute for war in its
function as the uniquely human system of population control must ensure the
survival, if not necessarily the improvement, of the species, in terms of its
relations to environmental supply.
-
CULTURAL AND SCIENTIFIC. A surrogate for
the function of war as the determinant of cultural values must establish a basis
of sociomoral conflict of equally compelling force and scope. A substitute
motivational basis for the quest for scientific knowledge must be similarly
informed by a comparable sense of internal necessity.
SUBSTITUTES FOR THE FUNCTIONS OF WAR: MODELS
The following substitute institutions, among
others, have been proposed for consideration as replacements for the nonmilitary
functions of war. That they may not have been originally set forth for that
purpose does not preclude or invalidate their possible application here.
-
ECONOMIC. a) A comprehensive
social-welfare program, directed toward maximum improvement of general
conditions of human life. b) A giant open-end space research program, aimed at
unreachable targets. c) A permanent, ritualized, ultra-elaborate disarmament
inspection system, and variants of such a system.
-
POLITICAL a) An omnipresent, virtually
omnipotent international police force. b) An established and recognized
extraterrestrial menace. c) Massive global environmental pollution. d)
Fictitious alternate enemies.
-
SOCIOLOGICAL: CONTROL FUNCTION. a)
Programs generally derived from the Peace Corps model. b) A modern,
sophisticated form of slavery. MOTIVATIONAL FUNCTION. a) Intensified
environmental pollution. b) New religions or other mythologies. c) Socially
oriented blood games. d) Combination forms.
-
ECOLOGICAL. A comprehensive program of
applied eugenics.
-
CULTURAL. No replacement institution
offered. SCIENTIFIC. The secondary requirements of the space research,
social welfare, and / or eugenics programs.
SUBSTITUTES FOR THE FUNCTIONS OF WAR:
EVALUATION
The models listed above reflect only the beginning
of the quest for substitute institutions for the functions of war, rather than a
recapitulation of alternatives. It would be both premature and inappropriate,
therefore, to offer final judgments on their applicability to a transition to
peace and after. Furthermore, since the necessary but complex project of
correlating the compatibility of proposed surrogates for different functions
could be treated only in exemplary fashion at this time, we have elected to
withhold such hypothetical correlations as were tested as statistically
inadequate.
Nevertheless, some tentative and cursory comments
on these proposed function-al "solutions" will indicate the scope of the
difficulties involved in this area of peace planning.
-
ECONOMIC. The social-welfare model cannot
be expected to remain outside the normal economy after the conclusion of its
predominantly capital-investment phase; its value in this function can therefore
be only temporary. The space-research substitute appears to meet both major
criteria, and should be examined in greater detail, especially in respect to its
probable effects on other war functions. "Elaborate inspection" schemes,
although superficially attractive, are inconsistent with the basic premise of a
transition to peace. The "unarmed forces" variant, logistically similar, is
subject to the same functional criticism as the general social-welfare model.
-
POLITICAL. Like the inspection-scheme
surrogates, proposals for plenipoteniary international police are inherently
incompatible with the ending of the war system. The "unarmed forces" variant,
amended to include unlimited powers of economic sanction, might conceivably be
expanded to constitute a credible external menace. Development of an acceptable
threat from "outer space," presumably in conjunction with a space-research
surrogate for economic control, appears unpromising in terms of credibility. The
environmental-pollution model does not seem sufficiently responsive to immediate
social control, except through arbitrary acceleration of current polution
trends; this in turn raises questions of political acceptability. New, less
regressive, approaches to the creation of fictitious global "enemies" invite
further investigation.
-
SOCIOLOGICAL: CONTROL FUNCTION. Although
the various substitutes proposed for this function that are modeled roughly on
the Peace Corps appear grossly inadequate in potential scope, they should not be
ruled out without further study. Slavery, in a technologically modern and
conceptually euphemized form, may prove a more efficient and flexible
institution in this area. MOTIVATIONAL FUNCTION. ALthough none of the
proposed substitutes for war as the guarantor of social allegiance can be
dismissed out of hand, each presents serious and special difficulties.
Intensified environmental threats may raise ecological dangers; mythmaking
dissociated from tar may no longer be politically feasible; purposeful blood
games and rituals can far more readily be devised than implemented. An
institution combining this function with the preceding one, based on, but not
necessarily imitative of, the precedent of organized ethnic repression, tarrants
careful consideration.
-
ECOLOGICAL. The only apparent problem in
the application of an adequate eugenic substitute for war is that of timing; it
cannot be effectuated until the transition to peace has been completed, which
involved a serious temporary risk of ecological failure.
-
CULTURAL. No plausible substitute for this
function of war has yet been proposed. It may be, however, that a basic cultural
value-determinant is not necessary to the survival of a stable society.
SCIENTIFIC. The same might be said for the function of war as the prime
mover of the search for knowledge. However, adoption of either a giant
space-research program, a comprehensive social-welfare program, or a master
program of eugenic control would provide motivation for limited technologies.
GENERAL CONCLUSIONS
It is apparent, from the foregoing, that no program
or combination of programs yet proposed for a transition to peace has remotely
approached meeting the comprehensive functional requirements of a world without
war. Although one projected system for filling the economic function of war
seems promising, similar optimism cannot be expressed in the equally essential
political and sociological areas. The other major nonmilitary functions of
war---ecological, cultural, scientific---raise very different problems, but it
is least possible that detailed programming of substitutes in these areas is not
prerequisite to transition. More important, it is not enough to develop adequate
but separate surrogates for the major war functions; they must be fully
compatible and in no degree self-canceling.
Until such a unified program is developed, at least
hypothetically, it is impossible for this or any other group to furnish
meaningful answers to the questions originally presented to us. When asked how
best to prepare for the advent of peace, we must first reply, as strongly as we
can, that the war system cannot responsibly be allowed to disappear until 1) we
know exactly what it is we plan to put in its place, and 2) we are certain,
beyond reasonable doubt, that these substitute institutions will serve their
purposes in terms of the survival and stability of society. It will then be time
enough to develop methods for effectuating the transition; procedural
programming must follow, not precede, substantive solutions.
Such solitions, if indeed they exist, will not be
arrived at without a revolutionary revision of the modes of thought heretofore
considered appropriate to peace research. That we have examined the fundamental
questions involved from a dispassionate, value-free point of view should not
imply that we do not appreciate the intellectual and emotional difficulties that
must be overcome on all decision-making levels before these questions are
generally acknowledged by others for what they are. They reflect, on an
intellectual level, traditional emotional resistance to new (more lethal and
thus more "shocking") forms of weaponry. The understated comment of then-Senator
Hubert Humphrey on the pub- lication of ON THERMONUCLEAR WAR is still
very mcuh to the point: "New Thoughts, particularly those which appear to
contradict current assumptions, are always painful for the mind to
contemplate."
Nor, simple because we have not discussed them, do
we minimize the massive reconciliation of conflicting interests with domestic as
well as international agreement on proceeding toward genuine peace presupposes.
This factor was excluded from the purview of our assignment, but we would be
remiss if we failed to take it into account. Although no insuperable obstacle
lies in the path of reaching such general agreements, formidable short-term
private-group and general-class interest in maintaining the war system is well
established and widely recognized. The resistance to peace stemming from such
interest is only tangential, in the long run, to the basic functions of war, but
it will not be easily overcome, in this country or elsewhere. Some observers, in
fact, believe that it cannot be overcome at all in our time, that the price of
peace is, simply, too high. This bears on our overall conclusions to the extent
that timing in the transference to substitute institutions may often be the
critical factor in their political feasibility.
It is uncertain, at this time, whether peace will
ever be possible. It is far more questionable, by the objective standard of
continued social survival rather than that of emotional pacifism, that it would
be desirable even if it were demonstrably attainable. The war system, for all
its subjective repugnance to important sections of "public opinion" has
demonstrated its effectiveness since the beginning of recorded history; it has
provided the basis for the development of many impressively durable
civilizations, including that which is dominant today. It has consistently
provided unambiguous social priorities. It is, on the whole, a known quantity. A
viable system of peace, assuming that the great and complex questions of
substitute institutions raised in this Report are both soluble and solved, would
still constitute a venture into the unknown, with the inevitable risks attendant
on the unforeseen, however small and however well hedged.
Government decision-makers tend to choose peace
over war whenever a real option exists, because it usually appears to be the
"safer" choice. Under most immediate circumstances they are likely to be right.
But in terms of long-range social stability, the opposite is true. At our
present state of knowledge and reasonable inference, it is the war system that
must be identified with stability, the peace system that must be identified with
social speculation, however justifiable the speculation may appear, in terms of
subjective moral or emotional values. A nuclear physicist once remarked, in
respect to a possible disarmament agreement: "If we could change the world into
a world in which no weapons could be made, that would be stabilizing. But
agreements we can expect with the Soviets would be destabilizing." The
qualification and the bias are equally irrelevant; any condition of genuine
total peace, however achieved, would be destabilizing until proved
otherwise.
If it were necessary at this moment to opt
irrevocably for the retention or for the dissolution of the war system, common
prudence would dictate the former course. But it is not yet necessary, late as
the hour appears. And more factors must eventually enter the war-peace equation
than even the most determined search for alternative institutions for the
functions of war can be expected to reveal. One group of such factors has been
given only passing mention in this Report; it centers around the possible
obsolescence of the war system itself. We have noted, for instance, the
limitations of the war system in filling its ecological function and the
declining importance of this aspect of war. It by no means stretches the
imagination to visualize comparable developments which may compromise the
efficacy of war as, for example, an economic controller or as an organizer of
social allegiance. This kind of possibility, however remote, serves as a
reminder that all calculations of contingency not only involve the weighing of
one group of risks against another, but require a respectful allowance for error
on both sides of the scale.
More expedient reason for pursuing the
investigation of alternate ways and means to serve the current functions of war
is narrowly political. It is possible that one or more major sovereign nations
may arrive, through ambiguous leadership, at a position in which a ruling
administrative class may lose control of basic public opinion or of its ability
to rationalize a desired war. It is not hard to imagine, in such circumstances,
a situation in which such governments may feel forced to initiate serious
full-scale disarmament proceed- ings (perhaps provoked by "accidental" nuclear
explosions), and that such nego- tiations may lead to the actual
disestablishment of military institutions. As our Report has made clear, this
could be catastrophic. It seems evident that, in the event an important part of
the world is suddenly plunged without suffi- cient warning into an inadvertent
peace, even partial and inadequate prepara- tion for the possibility may be
better than none. The difference could even be critical. The models considered
in the preceding chapter, both those that seem promising and those that do not,
have one positive feature in common--an inher- ent flexibility of phasing. And
despite our strictures against knowingly pro- ceeding into peace-transition
procedures without thorough substantive prepara- tion, our government must
nevertheless be ready to move in this direction with whatever limited resources
of planning are on hand at the time---if circum- stances so require>. An
arbitrary all-or-nothing approach is no more realistic in the development of
contingency peace programming than it is anywhere else.
But the principal cause for concern over the
continuing effectiveness of the war system, and the more important reason for
hedging with peace planning, lies in the backwardness of current war-system
programming. Its controls have not kept pace with the technological advances it
has made possible. Despite its unarguable success to date, even in this era of
unprecedented potential in mass destruction, it continues to operate largely on
a laissez-faire basis. To the best of our knowledge, no serious quantified
studies have even been conducted to determine, for example:
-
---optimum levels of armament production, for
purposes of economic control, at any given relationship between civilian
production and consumption patterns:
-
---correlation factors between draft recruitment
policies and mensurable social dissidence;
-
---minimum levels of population destruction
necessary to maintain war-threat credibility under varying political conditions;
-
---optimum cyclical frequency of "shooting" wars
under varying circumstances of historical relationship.
These and other war-function factors are fully
susceptible to analysis by today's computer-based systems, but they have not
been so treated; modern ana- lytical techniques have up to now been relegated to
such aspects of the osten- sible functions of war as procurement, personnel
deployment, weapons analysis, and the like. We do not disparage these types of
application, but only deplore their lack of utilization to greater capacity in
attacking problems of broader scope. Our concern for efficiency in this context
is not aesthetic, economic, or humanistic. It stems from the axiom that no
system can long survive at either input or output levels that consistently or
substantially deviate from an optimum range. As their data grow increasingly
sophisticated, the war system and its functions are increasingly endangered by
such deviations.
Our final conclusion, therefore, is that it will be
necessary for our govern- ment to plan in depth for two general contingencies.
The first, and lesser, is the possibility of a viable general peace; the second
is the successful contin- uation of the war system. In our view, careful
preparation for the possibility of peace should be extended, not because we take
the position that the end of war would necessarily be desirable, if it is in
fact possible, but because it may be thrust upon us in some form whether we are
ready for it or not. Planning for rationalizing and quantifying the war system,
on the other hand, to ensure the effectiveness of its major stabilizing
functions, is not only more promis- ing in respect to anticipated results, but
is essential; we can no longer take for granted that it will continue to serve
our purposes well merely because it always has. The objective of government
policy in regard to war and peace, in this perios of uncertainty, must be to
preserve maximum options. The recomenda- tions which follow are directed to this
end.
SECTION 8
RECOMMENDATIONS
-
We propose the establishment, under executive order
of the President, of a permanent WAR/PEACE Research Agency, empowered and
mandated to execute the programs described in (2) and (3) below. This agency (a)
will be provided with nonaccountable funds sufficient to implement its
responsibilities and decisions at its own discretion, and (b) will have
authority to preempt and utilize, without restriction, any and all facilities of
the executive branch of the government in pursuit of its objectives. It will be
organized along the lines of the National Security Council, except that none of
its governing, executive, or operating personnel will hold other public office
or governmental responsibility. Its directorate will be drawn from the broadest
practicable spectrum of scientific disciplines, humanistic studies, applied
creative arts, operating technologies, and otherwise unclassified professional
occupations. It will be responsible solely to the President, or to other
officers of government temporarily deputized by him. Its operations will be
governed entirely by its own rules of procedure. Its authority will expressly
include the unlimited right to withhold information on its activities and its
decisions, from anyone except the President, whenever it deems such secrecy to
be in the public interest.
-
The first of the War/Peace Research Agency's two
principal responsibilities will be to determine all that can be known, including
what can reasonably be inferred in terms of relevant statistical probabilities,
that may bear on an eventual transition to a general condition of peace. The
findings in this Report may be considered to constitute the beginning of this
study and to indicate its orientation; detailed records of the investigations
and findings of the Special Study Group on which this Report is based, will be
furnished the agency, along with whatever clarifying data the agency deems
necessary. This aspect of the agency's work will hereinafter be referred to as
"Peace Research."
The Agency's Peace Research activities will
necessarily include, but not be limited to, the following:
-
(a) The creative development of possible substitute
institutions for the principal nonmilitary functions of war.
-
(b) The careful matching of such institutions
against the criteria summarized in this Report, as refined, revised, and
extended by the agency.
-
(c) The testing and evaluation of substitute
institutions, for acceptability, feasibility, and credibility, against
hypothecated transitional and postwar conditions; the testing and evaluation of
the effects of the anticipated atrophy of certain unsubstantiated
functions.
-
(d) The development and testing of the corelativity
of multiple substitute institutions, with the eventual objective of establishing
a comprehensive program of compatible war substitutes suitable for a planned
transition to peace, if and when this is found to be possible and subsequently
judged desirable by appropriate political authorities.
-
(e) The preparatin of a wide-ranging schedule of
partial, uncorrelated, crash programs of adjustment suitable for reducing the
dangers of unplanned transition to peace effected by force majeure.
Peace Research methods will include but not be
limited to, the following:
-
(a) The comprehensive interdisciplinary application
of historical, scientific, technological, and cultural data.
-
(b) The full utilization of modern methods of
mathematical modeling, analo- gical analysis, and other, more sophisticated,
quantitative techniques in process of development that are compatible with
computer programming.
-
(c) The heuristic "peace games" procedures
developed during the course of its assignment by the Special Study Group, and
further extensions of this basic approach to the testing of institutional
functions.
-
The WAR/PEACE Research Agency's other principal
responsibility will be "War Research." Its fundamental objective will be to
ensure the continuing viability of the war system to fulfill its essential
nonmilitary functions for as long as the war system is judged necessary to or
desirable for the survival of society. To achieve this end, the War Research
groups within the agency will engage in the following activities:
-
(a) Quantification of existing application of the
non-military functions of war. Specific determinations will include, but not be
limited to:
-
the gross amount and the net proportion of
nonproductive military expenditures since World War II assignable to the need
for war as an economic stabilizer;
-
the amount and proportion of military expenditures
and destructin of life, property, and natural resources during this period
assignable to the need for war as an instrument for political control;
-
similar figures, to the extent that they can be
separately arrived at, assignable to the need for war to maintain social
cohesiveness;
-
levels of recruitment and expenditures on the draft
and other forms of personnel deployment attributable to the need for military
institutions to control social disaffectin;
-
the statistical relationship of war casualties to
world food supplies;
-
the correlation of military actions and
expenditures with cultural activities and scientific advances (including
necessarily the development of mensurable standards in these areas).
-
(b) Establishment of a priori modern criteria for
the execution of the non- military functions of war. These will include, but not
be limited to:
-
calculation of minimum and optimum ranges of
military expenditure required, under varying hypothetical conditions, to fulfill
these several functions, separately and collectively;
-
determination of minimum and optimum levels of
destruction of LIFE, PROPERTY, and NATURAL RESOURCES
prerequisite to the credibility of external threat essential to the political
and motivational functions;
-
development of a negotiable formula governing the
relationship between military recruitment and training policies and the
exigencies of social control.
-
(c) Reconciliation of these criteria with
prevailing economic, political, sociological, and ecological limitations. The
ultimate object of this phase of War Research is to rationalize the heretofore
informal operations of the war system. It shoud provide practical working
procedures through which responsible governmental authority may resolve the
following war-function problems, among others, under any given circumstances:
-
how to determine the optimum quantity, nature, and
timing of military expenditures to ensure a desired degree of economic control;
-
how to organize the recruitment, deployment, and
ostensible use of military personnel to ensure a desired degree of acceptance of
authorized social values;
-
how to compute on a short-term basis, the nature
and extent of the LOSS OF LIFE and other resources which SHOULD BE
SUFFERED and/or INFLICTED DURING any single outbreako of
hostilities to achieve a desired degree of internal political authority and
social allegiance;
-
how to project, over extended periods, the nature
and quality of overt warfare which must be planned and budgeted to achieve a
desired degree of contextual stability for the same purpose; factors to be
determined must include frequency of occurence, length of phase, INTENSITY
OF PHYSICAL DESTRUCTION, extensiveness of geographical involvement, and
OPTIMUM MEAN LOSS OF LIFE;
-
how to extrapolate accurately from the foregoing,
for ecological purposes, the continuing effect of the war system, over such
extended cycles, on population pressures, and to adjust the planning of casualty
rates accordingly.
War Research procedures will necessarily
include, but not be limited to, the following:
-
(a) The collation of economic, military, and other
relevant date into uniform terms, permitting the reversible translation of
heretofore discrete categories of information.
-
(b) The development and application of appropriate
forms of cost-effectiveness analysis suitable for adapting such new constructs
to computer terminology, programming, and projection.
-
(c) Extension of the "war games" methods of systems
testing to apply, as a quasi-adversary proceeding, to the nonmilitary functions
of war.
-
Since Both Programs of the WAR/PEACE RESEARCH
Agency will share the same purpose---to maintain governmental freedom of choice
in respect to war and peace until the direction of social survival is no longer
in doubt -- it is of the essence of this proposal that the agency be constituted
without limitation of time. Its examination of existing and proposed
institutions will be self-liquidating when its own function shall have been
superseded by the historical developments it will have, at least in part,
initiated.
NOTES.........
SECTION 1
1. The Economic and Social Consequences of
Disarmament: U.S.Reply to the Inquiry of the Secretary-General of the United
Nations (Washington, D.C.: USGPO, June 1964), pp. 8-9.
2. Herman Kahn, Thinking About the Unthinkable (New
York: Horizon, 1962), p.35.
3. Robert S. McNamara, in an address before the
American Society of News- paper Editors, in Montreal, P.Q., Canada, 18 May
1966.
4. Alfred North Whitehead, in "The Anatomy of Some
Scientific Ideas," in- cluded in The Aims of Education (New York: Macmillan,
1929).
5. At Ann Arbor, Michigan, 16 June 1962.
6. Louis J. Halle, "Peace in Our Time? Nuclear
Weapons as a Stabilizer," The New Republic (28 December 1963).
SECTION 2
1. Kenneth E. Boulding, "The World War Industry as
an Economic Problem," in Emile Benoit and Kenneth E. Boulding (eds.),
Disarmament and the Economy (New York: Harper & Row, 1963).
2. McNamara, in ASNE Montreal address cited.
3. Report of the Committee on the Economic Impact
of Defense and Disarmament (Washington: USGPO, July 1965).
4. Sumner M. Rosen, "Disarmament and the Economy,"
War/Peace Report (March 1966).
SECTION 3
1. Vide William D. Grampp, "False Fears of
Disarmament," Harvard Business Review (Jan.-Feb.1964) for a concise example of
this reasoning.
2. Seymour Melman, "The Cost of Inspection for
Disarmament," in Benoit and Boulding, op. cit.
SECTION 5
1. Arthur I. Waskow, Toward the Unarmed Forces of
the United States (Wash- ington: Institute for Policy Studies, 1966), p.9. (This
is the unabridged edition of the text of a report and proposal prepared for a
seminar of strate- gists and Congressman in 1965; it was later given limited
distribution among other persons engaged in related projects.)
2. David T. Bazelon, "The Politics of the Paper
Economy," Commentary (Nov- ember 1962), p.409.
3. The Economic Impact of Disarmament (Washington:
USGPO, January 1962), p.409.
4. David T. Bazelon, "The Scarcity Makers,"
Commentary (October 1962), p. 298.
5. Frank Pace, Jr., in an address before the
American Banker's Association, September 1957.
6. A random example, taken in this case from a
story by David Deitch in the New York Herald Tribune (9 February 1966).
7. Vide L. Gumplowicz, in Geschichte der
Staatstheorien (Innsbruck: Wagner, 1905) and earlier writings.
8. K.Fischer, Das Militar (Zurich: Steinmetz
Verlag, 1932), pp.42-43.
9. The obverse of this phenomenon is responsible
for the principal combat problem of present-day infantry officers: the
unwillingness of otherwise "trained" troops to fire at an enemy close enough to
be recognizable as an individual rather than simply as a target.
10. Herman Kahn, On Thermonuclear War (Princeton,
N.J., Princeton University Press, 1960), p.42. 11. John D. Williams, "The
Nonsense about Safe Driving," Fortune (September 1958).
12. Vide most recently K.Lorenz, in Das Sogenannte
Bose: zur Naturgeschichte der Agression (Vienna: G. Borotha-Schoeler Verlag,
1964).
13. Beginning with Herbert Spencer and his
contemporaries, but largely ignor- ed for nearly a century.
14. As in recent draft-law controversy, in which
the issue of selective deferment of the culturally privileged is often
carelessly equated with the preservation of the biologically "fittest."
15. G.Bouthol, in La Guerre (Paris: Presses
universitairies de France, 1953) and many other more detailed studies. The
useful concept of "polemology," for the study of war as an independent
discipline, is his, as is the notion of "demographic relaxation," the sudden
temporary decline in the rate of popula- tion increase after major wars.
16. This seemingly premature statement is supported
by one of our own test studies. But it hypothecates both the stabilizing of
world population growth and the institution of fully adequate environmental
controls. Under these two conditions, the probability of the permanent
elimination of involuntary global famine is 68 percent by 1976 and 95 percent by
1981.
SECTION 6
1. This round figure is the median taken from our
comuptations, which cover varying contingencies, but it is sufficient for the
purpose of general dis- cussion.
2. But less misleading than the more elegant
traditional metaphor, in which war expenditures are referred to as the "ballast"
of the economy but which suggests incorrect quantitative relationships.
3. Typical in generality, scope, and rhetoric. We
have not used any pub- lished program as a model; similarities are unavoidably
coincidental rather than tendentious.
4. Vide the reception of a "Freedom Budget for all
Americans," proposed by A. Philip Randolph et al; it is a ten-year plan,
estimated by its sponsors to cost $185 billion.
5. Waskow, op.cit.
6. By several current theorists, most extensively
and effectively by Robert R. Harris in "The Real Enemy," an unpublished doctoral
dissertation made avail- able to this study.
7. In ASNE, Montreal address cited.
8. The Tenth Victim.
9. For an examination of some of its social
implications, see Seymour Ruben- feld, Family of Outcasts: A New Theory of
Delinquency (New York: Free Press, 1965).
10. As in Nazi Germany; this type of "ideological"
ethnic repression, direc- ted to specific sociological ends, should not be
confused with traditional economic exploitation, as of Negroes in the U.S.,
South Africe, etc.
11. By teams of experimental biologists in
Massachusetts, Michigan, and California, as well as in Mexico and the U.S.S.R.
Preliminary test applications are scheduled in Southeast Asia, in countries not
yet announced.
12. Expressed in the writings of H. Marshall
McLuban, in Understanding Media: The Extensions of Man (New York: McGraw-Hill,
1964) and elsewhere.
13. This rather optimistic estimate was derived by
plotting a three-dimen- sional distribution of three arbitratily defined
variables; the macro-structur- al, relating to the extension of knowledge beyond
the capacity of conscious experience; the organic, dealing with the
manifestations of terrestrial life as inherently comprehensibel; and the
infra-particular, covering the subconcep- tual requirements of natural
phenomena. Values were assigned to the known and unknown in each parameter,
tested against data from earlier chronologies, and modified heuristically until
predictable correlations reached a useful level of accuracy. "Two decades"
means, in this case, 20.6 years, with a standard deviation of only 1.8 years.
(An incidental finding, not pursued to the same degree of accuracy, suggests a
greatly accelerated resolution of issues in the biological sciences after
1972.)
SECTION 7
1. Since they represent an examination of too small
a percentage of the eventual options, in terms of "multiple mating," the
subsystem we developed for this application. But an example will indicate how
one of the most frequen- tly recurring correlation problems--chronological
phasing--was brought to light in this way. One of the first combinations tested
showed remarkably high coefficients of compatibility, on a post hoc static
basis, but no variations of timing, using a thirty-year transition module,
permitted even marginal synchronization. The combination was thus disqualified.
This would not rule out the possible adequacy of combinations using
modifications of the same fac- tors, however, since minor variations in a
proposed final condition may have disproportionate effects on phasing.
2. Edward Teller, quoted in War/Peace Report
(December 1964).
3. E.g., the highly publicized "Delphi Technique"
and other, more sophisti- cated procedures. A new system, especially suitable
for institutional analysis, was developed during the course of this study in
order to hypothecate mensur- able "peace games"; a manual of this system is
being prepared and will be sub- mitted for general distribution among
appropriate agencies. For older, but still useful, techniques, see Norman C.
Dalkey's Games and Simulations (Santa Monica, Calif.:Rand, 1964).
SECTION 8
1. A primer-level example of the obvious and long
overdue need for such translation is furnished by Kahn (in Thinking About the
Unthinkable,p.102). Under the heading "Some Awkward Choices" he compares four
hypothetical poli- cies: a certain loss of $3,000; a .1 chance of loss of
$300,000; a.01 chance of loss of $30,000,000; and a .001 chance of loss of
$3,000,000,000. A government decision-maker would "very likely" choose in that
order. But what if "lives are at stake rather than dollars?" Kahn suggests that
the order of choice would be reversed, although current experience does not
support this opinion. Rational war research can and must make it possible to
express, without ambiguity, lives in terms of dollars and vice versa; the
choices need not be, and cannot be, "awkward."
2. Again, an overdue extension of an obvious
application of techniques up to now limited such circumscribed purposes as
improving kill-ammunition ratios determining local choice between precision and
saturation bombing, and other minor tactical, and occasionally strategic, ends.
The slowness of Rand, I.D.A., and other responsible analytic organizations to
extend cost-effectiveness and related concepts beyond early-phase applications
has already been widely re- marked on and critized elsewhere.
3. The inclusion of institutional factors in
war-game techniques has been given some rudimentary consideratin in the Hudson
Institute's Study for Hypo- thetical Narratives for Use in Command and Control
Systems Planning (by William Pfaff and Edmund Stillman; Final report published
in 1963). But here, as with other war and peace studies to date, what has
blocked the logical extension of new analytic techniques has been a general
failure to understand and properly evaluate the non-military functions of
war.
-EOF-
|